Still working to recover. Please don't edit quite yet.
Difference between revisions of "ad hominem"
Anarchangel (Talk | contribs) (....Does not quite deserve the AP tag yet, but I got some of the most obviously noisome lawyering out of the lead) |
Anarchangel (Talk | contribs) (...Clarifying, hopefully, sentence) |
||
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | An '''''ad hominem''''' ([[Wikipedia:Latin|Latin]]: "to the man"), also known as '''''argumentum ad hominem''''', is an attempt to link the [[validity]] [[Wikipedia:validity|(WP)]] of a [[premise]] [[Wikipedia:premise|(WP)]] to a characteristic or belief of the person advocating the premise.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.answers.com/topic/ad-hominem |title=ad hominem: West's Encyclopedia of American Law (Full Article) from |publisher=Answers.com |date=2007-09-10 |accessdate=2009-11-08}}</ref> | + | {{AP ED}} |
+ | An '''''ad hominem''''' ([[Wikipedia:Latin|Latin]]: "to the man"), also known as '''''argumentum ad hominem''''', is an attempt to link the [[validity]] [[Wikipedia:validity|(WP)]] of a [[premise]] [[Wikipedia:premise|(WP)]] to a characteristic or belief of the person advocating the premise.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.answers.com/topic/ad-hominem |title=ad hominem: West's Encyclopedia of American Law (Full Article) from |publisher=Answers.com |date=2007-09-10 |accessdate=2009-11-08}}</ref> Argumentum ad hominem is a relative latecomer to the ranks of the [[logical fallacy|logical fallacies]]; although concepts similar to it can be traced to [[Aristotle]] [[Wikipedia:Aristotle|(WP)]], its name comes from Latin and its current meaning from the 17th Century and later, and it was not one of the classic [[fallacy|fallacies]] [[Wikipedia:fallacy|(WP)]] of the [[Classical Greek]] [[Wikipedia:Classical Greece|(WP)]] period of [[logic]].<ref name="one">{{cite book|author= Doug Walton |title= Informal Logic: A Pragmatic Approach|year=2008|publisher=Cambridge University Press|pages=190 pp}}</ref> | ||
− | + | Ad Hominem shares a basic premise with other analyses of logical fallacies: qualities of a part of something under consideration should be the only qualities of the only part to be considered. An ad hominem error, specifically, is considering a characteristic of a person when their arguments are under consideration. | |
+ | Ad hominem is always a faulty argument in purely logical terms, but there are two major areas of the state that turn a blind eye to this, and [http://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/obfuscate obfuscate] the resultant indiscretions carefully, in [[sophistry]]: [[law]] and [[politics]]. Or oftentimes, less carefully, in separate statements that contradict each other, as in this version of the opening paragraph of [[Wikipedia:Conflict of interest]]: "The presence of a conflict of interest is independent from the execution of impropriety. Therefore, a conflict of interest can be discovered and voluntarily defused before any corruption occurs." The first sentence has it that the act of impropriety itself is not under consideration (handy, so that it cannot be accused of punishing [[Thoughtcrime]]); the second, that this rule will prevent any acts of impropriety (and woops, Thoughtcrime is back again, as those who support COI could not hold themselves back from touting the benefits they perceive in it). | ||
+ | |||
+ | In [[Wikipedia:law|law]], questions of personal conduct, character, motives, etc., are allowed as [[Wikipedia:Character evidence|Character evidence]]. In politics, [[Conflict of interest]], and in the UK, the particularly contentious [[Prejudicial interest]], attempt in vain to address inequalities whose true source is elsewhere; they are not only ad hominem but seek to prevent crimes that may never be attempted.<ref>{{cite book|authorlink= Wikipedia:Doug Walton |title= Informal Logic: A Pragmatic Approach |year=2008 |publisher= Cambridge University Press|pages=170 pp}}</ref> Prejudicial interest is in peril of being untenable, there is a perception that it has problems, and these problems are being addressed by the UK legislature. To what conclusion, is unknown. On Wikipedia, the rule of [[Wikipedia:WP:COI|Conflict of interest]] began as [[Wikipedia:WP:Wikipedia is not a vanity press]], where it properly concerned itself with the Non Point of View ([[Wikipedia:WP:NPOV]]) requirements that are now sometimes called [[Wikipedia:WP:PEACOCK]]. It now is an entirely unnecessary (because the only harm that COI users can do is already covered in other rules such as NPOV) ad hominem attack and also, in lockstep with the post-[[War on Imperialism]] special police powers worldwide, releases personal details of Wikipedia users ([[Wikipedia:WP:OUTING]]) at an alarming rate. There is a considerably lower standard of evidence in these areas than there is in formal logic. And finally, it may be noted that in an egalitarian society, there can be no such thing as conflict of interest. | ||
+ | |||
+ | == History == | ||
+ | Ad hominem had its roots in works of [[Wikipedia:Aristotle|Aristotle]], the Greek philosopher. [[Wikipedia:Gabriel Nuchelmans|Gabriël Nuchelmans]] holds that there are separate and distinct strands of meaning that have proceeded throughout history from Aristotle.<ref name=EL>[http://books.google.com/books?id=9Objpv2xOdQC&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=false Empirical logic and public debate: essays in honour of Else M. Barth], Chapters 3 and 4, page 39- Erik C. W. Krabbe, Renée José Dalitz, E. M. Barth </ref> The first two of these describe positive steps that can be taken in a logical argument, but are nonetheless concerned with responding to a qualities of another person, namely their points of view.<ref name=EL/> | ||
+ | |||
+ | One type emanates from Aristotle's own ''peirastiko logoi'', one of his four types of arguments (with dialectical, doctrinal or demonstrative, and eristic) which proposes that arguments be confined within the compass of the respondent's knowledge and views. Thus, paraphrases Nuchelmans, "we shall be able to converse with them setting out, not from views that others hold, but from their own views" This "peirastic" argument was called "disputatio temptativa" in Latin.<ref name=EL/> | ||
+ | |||
+ | Another describes the process of directing arguments at points that had been [[concede]]d by another. [[Wikipedia:Thomas Aquinus|Thomas Aquinus]] decided, in reading [[Wikipedia:Physics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's ''Physics'']], that it was not possible to provide a logical proof ([[Formal proof]]) [[Wikipedia:Formal proof|(WP)]] for someone who denied a [[principle]] [[Wikipedia:Principle|(WP)]] used as a premise of that proof; however, it was possible to prove something based on principles they believed or accepted.<ref name=EL/> | ||
+ | |||
+ | Aquinus' process is slightly more concerned with directing arguments than simply engaging in them efficiently, and the later developments of ad hominem changed slightly in the same way, past responding ''e concessis'', which itself started as arguing within another's points of concession and became arguing using conceded points whether or not they had merit. It is very tempting to attribute this prevalence of tactics over ethics to [[Rhetoric]]; while logic concerned itself with building roads along the journey of argumentation, rhetoric sought the quickest path to a single destination: winning.<ref name=EL/> | ||
+ | |||
+ | The development of this more rhetorical type of ad hominem began to be criticized as purely expedient and to be avoided, in the 16th and 17th centuries. More concretely, Arnold Geulincx in the 17th C showed how [[Wikipedia:Reductio ad absurdum]] was applied to others' arguments for another kind of ad hominem. At the same time, the ''e consessis'' and rhetorical varieties of ad hominem began to be conflated, until the modern, negative meaning became the sole survivor in common usage.<ref name=EL/> | ||
== Types == | == Types == |
Latest revision as of 22:17, 3 March 2011
An ad hominem (Latin: "to the man"), also known as argumentum ad hominem, is an attempt to link the validity (WP) of a premise (WP) to a characteristic or belief of the person advocating the premise.[1] Argumentum ad hominem is a relative latecomer to the ranks of the logical fallacies; although concepts similar to it can be traced to Aristotle (WP), its name comes from Latin and its current meaning from the 17th Century and later, and it was not one of the classic fallacies (WP) of the Classical Greek (WP) period of logic.[2]
Ad Hominem shares a basic premise with other analyses of logical fallacies: qualities of a part of something under consideration should be the only qualities of the only part to be considered. An ad hominem error, specifically, is considering a characteristic of a person when their arguments are under consideration.
Ad hominem is always a faulty argument in purely logical terms, but there are two major areas of the state that turn a blind eye to this, and obfuscate the resultant indiscretions carefully, in sophistry: law and politics. Or oftentimes, less carefully, in separate statements that contradict each other, as in this version of the opening paragraph of Wikipedia:Conflict of interest: "The presence of a conflict of interest is independent from the execution of impropriety. Therefore, a conflict of interest can be discovered and voluntarily defused before any corruption occurs." The first sentence has it that the act of impropriety itself is not under consideration (handy, so that it cannot be accused of punishing Thoughtcrime); the second, that this rule will prevent any acts of impropriety (and woops, Thoughtcrime is back again, as those who support COI could not hold themselves back from touting the benefits they perceive in it).
In law, questions of personal conduct, character, motives, etc., are allowed as Character evidence. In politics, Conflict of interest, and in the UK, the particularly contentious Prejudicial interest, attempt in vain to address inequalities whose true source is elsewhere; they are not only ad hominem but seek to prevent crimes that may never be attempted.[3] Prejudicial interest is in peril of being untenable, there is a perception that it has problems, and these problems are being addressed by the UK legislature. To what conclusion, is unknown. On Wikipedia, the rule of Conflict of interest began as Wikipedia:WP:Wikipedia is not a vanity press, where it properly concerned itself with the Non Point of View (Wikipedia:WP:NPOV) requirements that are now sometimes called Wikipedia:WP:PEACOCK. It now is an entirely unnecessary (because the only harm that COI users can do is already covered in other rules such as NPOV) ad hominem attack and also, in lockstep with the post-War on Imperialism special police powers worldwide, releases personal details of Wikipedia users (Wikipedia:WP:OUTING) at an alarming rate. There is a considerably lower standard of evidence in these areas than there is in formal logic. And finally, it may be noted that in an egalitarian society, there can be no such thing as conflict of interest.
Contents
History[edit]
Ad hominem had its roots in works of Aristotle, the Greek philosopher. Gabriël Nuchelmans holds that there are separate and distinct strands of meaning that have proceeded throughout history from Aristotle.[4] The first two of these describe positive steps that can be taken in a logical argument, but are nonetheless concerned with responding to a qualities of another person, namely their points of view.[4]
One type emanates from Aristotle's own peirastiko logoi, one of his four types of arguments (with dialectical, doctrinal or demonstrative, and eristic) which proposes that arguments be confined within the compass of the respondent's knowledge and views. Thus, paraphrases Nuchelmans, "we shall be able to converse with them setting out, not from views that others hold, but from their own views" This "peirastic" argument was called "disputatio temptativa" in Latin.[4]
Another describes the process of directing arguments at points that had been conceded by another. Thomas Aquinus decided, in reading Aristotle's Physics, that it was not possible to provide a logical proof (Formal proof) (WP) for someone who denied a principle (WP) used as a premise of that proof; however, it was possible to prove something based on principles they believed or accepted.[4]
Aquinus' process is slightly more concerned with directing arguments than simply engaging in them efficiently, and the later developments of ad hominem changed slightly in the same way, past responding e concessis, which itself started as arguing within another's points of concession and became arguing using conceded points whether or not they had merit. It is very tempting to attribute this prevalence of tactics over ethics to Rhetoric; while logic concerned itself with building roads along the journey of argumentation, rhetoric sought the quickest path to a single destination: winning.[4]
The development of this more rhetorical type of ad hominem began to be criticized as purely expedient and to be avoided, in the 16th and 17th centuries. More concretely, Arnold Geulincx in the 17th C showed how Wikipedia:Reductio ad absurdum was applied to others' arguments for another kind of ad hominem. At the same time, the e consessis and rhetorical varieties of ad hominem began to be conflated, until the modern, negative meaning became the sole survivor in common usage.[4]
Types[edit]
Abuse[edit]
Ad hominem abuse (WP) (also called personal abuse or personal attacks) usually involves Wikipedia:insulting or belittling one's opponent in order to invalidate his or her argument, but can also involve pointing out ostensible or even factual character flaws or actions. This tactic is logically fallacious because the source of an argument is not the argument.
Examples:
- "You can't believe Jack when he says the proposed policy would help the economy. He doesn't even have a job."
- "Candidate Jane's proposal about zoning is ridiculous. She was caught cheating on her taxes in 2003."
Circumstantial[edit]
Ad hominem circumstantial points out that someone is in circumstances such that he is disposed to take a particular position. Ad hominem circumstantial constitutes an attack on the bias of a source. This is fallacious because a disposition to make a certain argument does not make the argument false; this overlaps with the Wikipedia:genetic fallacy (an argument that a claim is incorrect due to its source).[5]
The circumstantial fallacy only applies where the source taking a position is only making a logical argument from premises that are generally accepted. Where the source seeks to convince an audience of the truth of a premise by a claim of authority or by personal observation, observation of their circumstances may reduce the evidentiary weight of the claims, sometimes to zero.[6]
Examples:
Wikipedia:Mandy Rice-Davies's famous testimony during the Wikipedia:Profumo Affair, "Well, he would [say that], wouldn't he?", is an example of a valid circumstantial argument. Her point was that since a man in a prominent position, accused of an affair with a Wikipedia:callgirl, would deny the claim whether it was true or false, his denial, in itself, carries little evidential weight against the claim of an affair. Note, however, that this argument is valid only insofar as it devalues the denial; it does not bolster the original claim. To construe evidentiary invalidation of the denial as evidentiary validation of the original claim is fallacious (on several different bases, including that of argumentum ad hominem); however likely the man in question would be to deny an affair that did in fact happen, he could only be more likely to deny an affair that never did.
Conflict of Interest: Where a source seeks to convince by a claim of authority or by personal observation, identification of conflicts of interest are not ad hominem - it is generally well accepted that an "authority" needs to be objective and impartial, and that an audience can only evaluate information from a source if they know about conflicts of interest that may affect the objectivity of the source. Identification of a conflict of interest is appropriate, and concealment of a conflict of interest is a problem.
Tu quoque[edit]
Ad hominem Wikipedia:tu quoque (lit: "You too!") refers to a claim that the source making the argument has spoken or acted in a way inconsistent with the argument. In particular, if Source A criticizes the actions of Source B, a tu quoque response is that Source A has acted in the same way. This argument is fallacious because it does not disprove the argument; if the premise is true then Source A may be a hypocrite, but this does not make the statement less credible from a logical perspective. Indeed, Source A may be in a position to provide personal testimony to support the argument.
For example, a father may tell his son not to start smoking as he will regret it when he is older, and the son may point out that his father is or was a smoker. This does not alter the fact that his son may regret smoking when he is older.
Guilt by association[edit]
Guilt by association can sometimes also be a type of ad hominem fallacy, if the argument attacks a source because of the similarity between the views of someone making an argument and other proponents of the argument.[7]
This form of the argument is as follows:
- Source S makes claim C.
- Group G, which is currently viewed negatively by the recipient, also makes claim C.
- Therefore, source S is viewed by the recipient of the claim as associated to the group G and inherits how negatively viewed it is.
Common misconceptions[edit]
W i k t i o n a r y Definitions, etymology, pronunciation of ad hominem |
Gratuitous Wikipedia:verbal abuse or "name-calling" itself is not an ad hominem or a logical fallacy.[8][9][10][11][12]
This is not to be confused with a true fallacy, which would be "X is idiotically ignorant [of politics], so why should we listen to him now?"
Identification of conflicts of interest - see "Circumstantial", above.
See also[edit]
References[edit]
- ↑ ad hominem: West's Encyclopedia of American Law (Full Article) from. Answers.com. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
- ↑ Doug Walton (2008). Informal Logic: A Pragmatic Approach, p. 190 pp, Cambridge University Press.
- ↑ (2008) Informal Logic: A Pragmatic Approach, p. 170 pp, Cambridge University Press.
- ↑ 4.0 4.1 4.2 4.3 4.4 4.5 Empirical logic and public debate: essays in honour of Else M. Barth, Chapters 3 and 4, page 39- Erik C. W. Krabbe, Renée José Dalitz, E. M. Barth
- ↑ Walton DN. Ad Hominem Arguments. University of Alabama Press, 1998. ISBN 0817309225, pp.18-21
- ↑ fallacyfiles.org (2007). Argumentum ad Hominem. fallacyfiles.org. URL accessed on September 10, 2007.
- ↑ Walton DN. Ad Hominem Arguments. University of Alabama Press, 1998. ISBN 0817309225, pp.18-21
- ↑ Ad Hominem. Plover.net. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
- ↑ Logical Fallacy: Argumentum ad Hominem. Fallacyfiles.org. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
- ↑ Logic Fallacies. The Autonomist. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
- ↑ AdHominem. Drury.edu. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
- ↑ Logical Fallacies» Ad Hominem (Personal Attack). Logicalfallacies.info. URL accessed on 2009-11-08.
Further reading[edit]
- Wikipedia:Patrick Hurley (2000). A Concise Introduction to Logic, Seventh Edition, p. 125–128, 182, Wikipedia:wadsworth, a division of Wikipedia:Thompson Learning.
- Copi, Irving M. and Cohen, Carl. Introduction to Logic (8th Ed.), p. 97-100.
- Wikipedia:Doug Walton (1998). Ad Hominem Arguments, p. 240 pp, Tuscaloosa: University Alabama Press.
External links[edit]
- Nizkor.org: Fallacy: Ad Hominem.
- Nizkor.org: Fallacy: Circumstantial Ad Hominem.
- Argumentum Ad Hominem
- the ad hominem fallacy fallacy
- University of Winnipeg: Argumentation Schemes and Historical Origins of the Circumstantial Ad Hominen Argument 70.2 KB application/pdf, 71948 bytes
- About.com: Argument Against the Person (Argumentum ad hominem)
- Logical Fallacies: Ad Hominem
- Infidels.org: Logic and Fallacies: Constructing a Logical Argument (Argumentum ad Hominem)
- Mission Critical: Introduction to Ad Hominem Fallacies
Template:Red Herring FallacyTemplate:PropagandaTemplate:AbuseTemplate:Bullyingsimple:Ad hominemzh-yue:人身攻擊謬誤