Still working to recover. Please don't edit quite yet.

Difference between revisions of "Anarcho-Capitalism"

From Anarchopedia
Jump to: navigation, search
(Criticism of Anarcho-capitalism)
 
(228 intermediate revisions by 73 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Libertarianism}}
+
{{Echo of Freedom|238000|Ownership of Self}}
  
'''Anarcho-capitalism''' is an [[anti-statism|anti-statist]] [[philosophy]] that embraces [[capitalism]] as one of its foundational principles. The first well-known version of anarcho-capitalism to identify itself with this term was developed by [[Austrian School]] economists and [[libertarians]] [[Murray Rothbard]] and [[Walter Block]] in the mid-[[20th century]] as an attempted synthesis of Austrian School [[economics]], classical [[liberalism]], and [[Individualist anarchism]].''
+
'''Anarcho-Capitalism''' is a movement self-decribing as an [[individualist anarchism|individualist anarchist]]<ref>Adams, Ian. 2002. Political Ideology Today. p. 135. Manchester University Press; Ostergaard, Geoffrey. 2003. Anarchism. In W. Outwaite (Ed.), ''The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought''. p. 14. Blackwell Publishing</ref> [[political philosophy]] that advocates the elimination of the [[state|state]] and the elevation of the [[individual]] in a [[free market]]. Anarchists that disagree with [[capitalism]] see the label as a contradiction in terms, disputing its inclusion in the spectrum of [[anarchism]].
  
Anarcho-capitalist philosophy as described by Rothbard is based on the idea of individual sovereignty (or "[[self-ownership]]"), an unlimited right to [[private property]], and a prohibition against the initiation of [[coercion]] or fraud against other persons or [[property]].  From this is derived a rejection of the [[state]] (an entity claiming a territorial monopoly on the use of force) and an acceptance of the principles of capitalism (a [[free market]] economy that includes private ownership of [[capital]] and pursuit of [[profit]].
+
Some anarcho-capitalists are fundamentally against proactive physical coercion; their system has no metanormative opposition to voluntary communism or syndicalism. Others prefer that in an anarcho-capitalist society, [[Police|law enforcement]], [[court]]s, any formerly state-provided institutions or services that consumers demanded would be provided by voluntarily-funded or voluntarily-formed organizations, with defense and security being provided by [[private defense agencies]] or communal militias rather than through taxation, and where [[commodity money|money]] is [[free banking|privately produced]] in an [[free market|open market]].
  
Because of this embrace of capitalism, there is considerable tension between anarcho-capitalists and anarchists who see the [[anti-capitalism|rejection of capitalism]] as being just as essential to [[anarchist]] philosophy as rejection of the state. Despite this tension, some anarcho-capitalists see their philosophy as evolving from the tradition of [[19th century]] [[United States|American]] individualist anarchism that includes classical liberal thinkers such as [[Lysander Spooner]].
+
Deontological anarcho-capitalists, such as Murray Rothbard, claim that no state is morally justified, and that the traditional functions of the state thus ought to be provided by voluntary human interaction. Others, such as David Friedman, claim that the state is economically and socially suboptimal and that non-physically coercive human interaction yields greater Marshallian efficiency.
  
Anarcho-capitalism can be considered a radical development of classical liberalism.  Its grounding in liberalism is demonstrated by the assertion of many anarcho-capitalists that the first anarcho-capitalist was [[Gustave de Molinari]], who argued for a free market, and against a state [[monopoly]] on force, as early as [[1849]]While some current adherents of [[liberalism]] and [[anarchism]] wouldn't call Molinari an anarcho-capitalist, his thoughts were influential on Rothbard and his contemporaries.
+
There are some anarcho-capitalists that do not view anarchism as requiring titles, but see it as an attitude with hyphenations merely describing the means by which they seek to attain anarchy; that is, where no human owns any human.  In fact, they are more properly described as anarchists and capitalists.  For instance, they view debt and monopolization as probabilities that could bring about archism, so anarchists use capitalistic methods to prevent or limit these, including to avoid business with those that do not follow ways to avoid archism, which stems from the idea that "activity produces wealth"For example, some refuse business with companies that are monopolistic or that are developing into a monopoly, and others also refuse trade with those that do not divest to an extent or release debtors every seven years, regardless of how much was owed.  Indeed, a few call themselves competists, rather than capitalists, as they view competition as necessary to obtain better products (or capital).
  
== Philosophy ==
+
==Theory==
{| align=right style="margin-left: 15px; text-align: left; border:3px solid #aaaaaa; padding:2px; font-size: 80%; width: 25%;" class=box
+
|bgcolor=#DBEAFF|
+
The term ''anarcho-capitalism'' was most likely coined in the mid-50s by the economist [[Murray Rothbard]]{{ref|Rothbard-1988}}.  Other terms used for this philosophy include:
+
*anti-state capitalism
+
*anarcho-liberalism
+
*[[market anarchism]]
+
*the private-law society {{ref|Hoppe-2001}}
+
*private-property anarchy {{ref|Hoppe-2001b}}
+
*radical capitalism {{ref|Hoppe-2001c}}
+
*right-anarchism {{ref|Wall-2004}}
+
*[[voluntaryism]]
+
|}
+
  
===  The Non-Aggression Axiom ===
+
Anarcho-capitalism is a consistent version of capitalism, where coercive public monopolies would no longer exist.
{{main| non-aggression axiom }}
+
Anarcho-capitalism, as formulated by Rothbard and others, holds strongly to the central libertarian "non-aggression axiom":
+
  
:''"[...] The basic axiom of libertarian political theory holds that every man is a [[self-ownership|selfowner]], having absolute jurisdiction over his own body. In effect, this means that no one else may justly invade, or aggress against, another's person. It follows then that each person justly owns whatever previously unowned resources he appropriates or 'mixes his labor with.' From these twin axioms&mdash;-self-ownership and 'homesteading'-stem the justification for the entire system of property rights titles in a free-market society. This system establishes the right of every man to his own person, the right of donation, of bequest (and, concomitantly, the right to receive the bequest or inheritance), and the right of contractual exchange of property titles."''{{ref|Rothbard-1982.1}} <!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/lawproperty.pdf (Rothbard 1982,1)] -->
+
Anarcho-Capitalism embraces the [[free market]], which contrasts with collectivistic anarchist philosophy. It should be noted that most anarcho-capitalists define the words "[[capitalism]]," "[[free market]]" and "private [[property]]" differently from collectivistic anarchists.
  
In general, the non-aggression axiom can be said to be a prohibition against the initiation of force, or the threat of force, against persons (i.e. direct violence, murder, assault) or property (i.e. theft, fraud, burglary, [[taxation]]).{{ref|Rothbard-1973}} <!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/newliberty.asp (Rothbard 1973, pp.24-25)] --> The initiation of force is usually referred to as [[aggression]] or [[coercion]]. The difference between anarcho-capitalists and other libertarians is largely one of the degree to which they take this axiom.  [[Minarchist]] libertarians, such as most people involved in [[Libertarian Party|Libertarian political parties]], would retain the state in some smaller and less invasive form, retaining public [[police]], [[courts]] and [[military]].  In contrast, anarcho-capitalists reject even that level of state intervention, defining any state as a coercive monopoly and, as the only entity in human society that derives it income from legal aggression, an entity that inherently violates the central axiom of libertarianism. {{ref|Rothbard-1982.2}} <!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/ethics/ethics.asp (Rothbard 1982,2 p162)] -->
+
* Capitalism: economic system where production is, at least, originally privately owned, where business decisions and correction are determined through the operation of a free market.
 +
* Free market: market where all decisions regarding transfer of possessions, including items and services, are voluntary.
 +
* Private possession (or property): possession gained by the invention of it, by mixing one's labor with unused and unpossessed material or material already owned by that person, by voluntary trade or as a gift.
  
{| align=left style="margin-right: 15px; text-align: left; border:3px solid #aaaaaa; padding:4px; font-size: 85%; width:240px;" class=box
+
This difference in terminology is often the basis for controversy.
|bgcolor=#DBEAFF|
+
Anarcho-capitalism uses the following terms in ways that may differ from common usage or various anarchist movements::
+
*'''Anarchy''' - a society without a State
+
*'''Contract''' &#8211; a voluntary agreement between persons
+
*'''Coercion''' &#8211; physical force or threat of such against persons or property
+
*'''Capitalism''' &#8211; economic system where the means of production are privately owned, and where investments, production, distribution, income, and prices are determined through the operation of a free market
+
*'''Free market''' &#8211; a market where all decisions regarding transfer of money, goods (including capital goods), and services are voluntary
+
*'''Fraud''' inducing one to part with something of value through the use of dishonesty
+
*'''State''' &#8211; an organization claiming a monopoly on use of coercion in a given geographic area
+
*'''Voluntary''' &#8211; any action not influenced by coercion or fraud perpetrated by any human agency
+
|}
+
  
=== Anarchism and Capitalism ===
+
Though the first self-described anarcho-capitalist was 19th century individualist anarchist Voltarine de Cleyre, anarcho-capitalism as a defined political philosophy did not emerge until the [[1950s]], coming out of the tradition of [[classical liberalism]], and generally setting itself in contrast to all forms of coercion and collectivism. [[Murray Rothbard]], an [[Austrian economist]] influenced by work of individualist anarchists like [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Lysander Spooner]], is often described as the founder of [[anarcho-capitalism]].
{{main|Anarchism and capitalism}}
+
  
Due to the fact that anarcho-capitalism is an [[anti-statist]] philosophy, rather than an [[anti-authoritarian]] one, most anarchists who follow in the [[mutualist]], [[individualist]], and [[collectivist]] traditions of anarchism strongly maintain that anarcho-capitalism is '''not''' a form of anarchy.  This is, in part, a terminological dispute that heavily relies on the user's definition of the word "anarchism".  The traditions that object to the term anarcho-capitalism tend to use the term "anarchism" to refer to a particular group of [[socialist]] political movements, and use a general definition that includes rejection of '''all''' hierarchical social organization, rather than just the state. They regard the uneven distribution of wealth among individuals in a capitalist system as inherently hierarchical.  Therefore, they see anarcho-capitalism as antithetical to the principles of anarchy.
+
=== Varying Views on Intellectual Property ===
  
According to [http://www.anarchy.no/ai.html The Anarchist International], capitalism is an economic plutarchy that includes its own hierarchy. They place anarcho-capitalism outside of the anarchist movement, and into the classical liberal tradition: "plutarchy without statism = liberalism."  They also view anarcho-capitalism as a serious misrepresentation of the core principles of anarchism, and disagree on definitions (see sidebar) as basic as what constitutes a "voluntary" action and what constitutes a "free market."  [[Anarcho-capitalism#Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism|(see: Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism) ]]
+
While some Anarcho-capitalists support [[intellectual property]], others oppose it, claiming that intellectual property infringes on physical property. They hold that intellectual property laws "in effect grant the holder the right to control the property and bodies of other people". [http://www.lewrockwell.com/blog/lewrw/archives/006393.html] These anarcho-capitalists consider intellectual property to be equivalent to [[mercantilism]], the system under which monarchs would grant exclusive monopolies to companies in a certain industry or territory.
  
Conversely, libertarians and anarcho-capitalists most commonly use the term &#8220;anarchism&#8221; with the more limited definition of an opposition to the existence of a state, favoring a society based on what they consider voluntary relations between individuals, accepting whatever social structures that evolve under such a system. This divide has been termed as [[left anarchism]] versus [[right anarchism]] by some individuals, such as Ulrike Heider.{{ref|Heider}} Anarcho-capitalists such as Murray Rothbard, in "Left and Right: The Prospects for Liberty," put anarcho-capitalism on the extreme left. Most contemporary anarchists reject the standard [[Left-Right politics|linear model of ideologies]], in favor of a 2-dimensional model with a liberty-authority dimension. The political ideology diagram shows a view of this [[political spectrum]] more in line with anarcho-capitalist philosophy.
+
Jeremy Sapienza, founder anti-state.com writes, "Is there nothing more preposterous than equating intellectual property, whatever the hell that is, with real, personal property?"[http://www.lewrockwell.com/sapienza/sapienza36.html].
  
[[Image:Ancap chart.JPG|375px|right|thumb|An anarcho-capitalist model of political ideologies. Liberty-Authority X Socialism-Capitalism.]]
+
Roderick T. Long argues that intellectual property violates the freedom of the speech and of the press:
 +
"To enforce copyright laws and the like is to prevent people from making peaceful use of the information they possess. If you have acquired the information legitimately (say, by buying a book), then on what grounds can you be prevented from using it, reproducing it, trading it? Is this not a violation of the freedom of speech and press?" [http://libertariannation.org/a/f31l1.html#1]
  
=== Original appropriation ===
+
In cases where anarcho-capitalists support intellectual property, it stems from the idea that property arrives from activity or labor, internal or external not being a subject of debate.
  
Central to anarcho-capitalism are the concepts of [[self-ownership]] and [[original appropriation]]:
+
Lysander Spooner, who supported copyright and patents, wrote in his THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY; OR AN ESSAY ON THE RIGHT OF AUTHORS AND INVENTORS TO A PERPETUAL PROPERTY IN THEIR IDEAS [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/intellect/contents.htm]: "man's ideas are his property. They are his for enjoyment, and his for use. Other men do not own his ideas. He has a right, as against all other men, to absolute dominion over his ideas....So absolute is the author’s right of dominion over his ideas that he may forbid their being communicated even by human voice if he so pleases".  [http://www.dailypaul.com/node/145162]
  
::''"Everyone is the proper owner of his own physical body as well as of all places and nature-given goods that he occupies and puts to use by means of his body, provided only that no one else has already occupied or used the same places and goods before him. This ownership of "originally appropriated" places and goods by a person implies his right to use and transform these places and goods in any way he sees fit, provided only that he does not change thereby uninvitedly the physical integrity of places and goods originally appropriated by another person. In particular, once a place or good has been first appropriated by, in [[John Locke]]&#8217;s phrase, 'mixing one&#8217;s labor' with it, ownership in such places and goods can be acquired only by means of a voluntary &#8211; contractual &#8211; transfer of its property title from a previous to a later owner."''{{ref|Hoppe-2002}} <!-- [http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe7.html (Hoppe 2002)] -->
+
Murray Rothbard, a defender of copyright but not patents, claimed, "Let us consider copyright. A man writes a book or composes music. When he publishes the book or sheet of music, he imprints on the first page the word “copyright.” This indicates that any man who agrees to purchase this product also agrees as part of the exchange not to recopy or reproduce this work for sale. In other words, the author does not sell his property out­right to the buyer; he sells it on condition that the buyer not reproduce it for sale. Since the buyer does not buy the property outright, but only on this condition, any infringement of the con­tract by him or a subsequent buyer is implicit theft and would be treated accordingly on the free market. The copyright is there­fore a logical device of property right on the free market....and this copyright would be per­petual, not limited to a certain number of years. Obviously, to be fully the property of an individual, a good has to be perma­nently and perpetually the property of the man and his heirs and assigns". [http://mises.org/rothbard/mes/chap10e.asp#7._Patents_Copyrights]
  
This is the root of anarcho-capitalist [[property rights]], and where they differ from [[collectivist]] forms of anarchismOriginal appropriation allows an individual to claim any "unused" property, including land, and by improving or otherwise using it, own it with the same absolute right as his own body.  As a practical matter, in terms of the ownership of land, anarcho-capitalists recognize that there are few (if any) parcels of land left on Earth whose ownership was not at some point in time transferred as the result of coercion, usually by seizure by some form of stateHowever, they do not believe that this history de-legitimizes current ownerships which are based on consensual transactions. They believe it is wrong to attempt to remedy past coercion by the use of present coercion. (i.e. seizure or eviction.)
+
In Linda and Morris Tannehill's "The Market for Liberty", they supported intellectual property in a number of waysIn their advocacy of private property, they state, "A man’s life is made up of time, so when he invests his time in material or intellectual property (ideas) he is investing parts of his life, thereby making that property an extension of his life." [http://alexpeak.com/twr/tmfl/ch2.html] In Chapter 7, they mention how free courts would be used to help an inventor in a conflict with "Handy-Dandy Kitchen Gadget". [http://alexpeak.com/twr/tmfl/ch7.html]
  
<!-- [[Image:Download la gold.jpg|thumb|left|The [[Libertatis Æquilibritas]] is a symbol of anarcho-capitalism.]] -->
+
The debate over intellectual property among anarcho-capitalists is still on-going.
  
By accepting an axiomatic definition of private property and property rights, anarcho-capitalists deny the legitimacy of a state on principle:
+
=== Wage Labor ===
  
::''"For, apart from ruling out as unjustified all activities such as murder, homicide, rape, trespass, robbery, burglary, theft, and fraud, the ethics of private property is also incompatible with the existence of a state defined as an agency that possesses a compulsory territorial monopoly of ultimate decision-making (jurisdiction) and/or the right to tax"''{{ref|Hoppe-2002b}} <!-- [http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe7.html (Hoppe 2002)] -->
+
Anarcho-capitalists state that an employer-employee relationship may be a mutually profitable form of voluntary association. They resent government as a parasite that corrupts, biases, impedes and distorts what would otherwise be peaceful fair and free associations.
  
=== The Contractual Society ===
+
Anarcho-capitalists consider that in consenting to a contract, that each party was free to refuse, the contract is voluntary and therefore legitimate and beneficial, claiming any external power that attempts to prevent such relationship is itself an oppression.
  
The society envisioned by anarcho-capitalists has been called the ''Contractual Society''; "[...] a society based purely on voluntary action, entirely un­hampered by violence or threats of violence."{{ref|Rothbard-1962}}<!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/mes/chap2a.asp (Rothbard 1962, ch2)] -->  Because this system relies on voluntary agreements ([[contract|contracts]]) between individuals as the only legal framework, it is difficult to predict precisely what the particulars of this society would look like.  Those particulars are disputed both among anarcho-capitalists and between anarcho-capitalists and their critics.
+
Anarcho-capitalists argue that, no matter what social organization may or may not exist, social organizations will never eliminate the basic human requirement to work in order to support themselves. Therefore an objection based on a constraint that cannot be overcome is useless to argue about and not a rational objection at all. Additionally, they argue that while someone may not be able to refuse to work in general, one has the largest diversity on the free market with regard to their employers or beginning their own business operation. What matters is that no given employer/employee contract be coercive. Thus, anarcho-capitalists believe that an individual may choose to work in any manner they wish, be it for a wage or for some other means of payment, so long as there is no coercion involved.
  
One particular ramification is that transfer of property and services must be voluntary on the part of '''both''' parties.  No external entities can force an individual to accept or deny a particular transaction.  An employer might offer insurance and death benefits to [[same-sex marriage|same-sex couples]]; another might refuse to recognize any union outside his or her own faith.  Individuals would be free to enter into contractual agreements as they saw fit, allowing discrimination or favoritism based on race, gender, language, sexual orientation, or any other categorization. Anarcho-capitalists maintain that the social structure would be self-regulating, since any disenfranchised group can avail themselves of [[boycott]] and/or [[protest]], and other entrepreneurs will see their own interests (i.e. profit) in servicing the group.
+
== Criticism of Anarcho-capitalism ==
 +
:&ldquo;[[freedom|Freedom]] without [[socialism|Socialism]] is privilege and injustice and Socialism without freedom is slavery and brutality.&rdquo; ~ [[Mihail Bakunin]]
 +
[[File:The anarchocapitalism.JPG|thumb|350 px|Some collectivist anarchist criticism of anarcho-capitalism resembles criticism of mainstream libertarianism]]
 +
Anarcho-capitalism is a view that departs from collectivistic anarchist theories in that it regards coercive public entities as unnecessary and harmful to human society, but embraces capitalist economics. Anarcho-capitalism contradicts collectivist [[anarchism]], an [[anti-capitalism|anti-capitalist]] philosophy. Anarcho-capitalism is often considered a paradox by collectivistic anarchists, and vice-versa.
  
Another important ramification is the fact that any social structure is permissible under anarcho-capitalism as long as it is formed by a contract between individuals.  Therefore, radically different "governments" and sub-economies can form, creating a [[Panarchism|panarchic]] society. Individuals could live in a privately owned [[democracy]], or [[republic]], or even a [[monarchy]], if they so choose.
+
Collectivist anarchists purport that there is no form of [[capitalism]] that does not rely on the concentration of wealth and the existence of [[private property]], and the need for defense of this property through public or private coercion. They claim that [[James Donald]] and [[Bryan Caplan]] have attempted (in the [[1990s]]) to frame their arguments in language and documents that appear to be legitimate, because they use certain [[power word|key phrases]] and structure and some author's attempts to have some connection to scholarly circles with anarchist legitimacy.
  
One social structure that is not permissible under anarcho-capitalism is one that attempts to claim greater [[sovereignty]] than the individuals that form it.  The state is a prime example, but another is the modern [[corporation]]&mdash; defined as a legal entity that exists under a different legal code than individuals as a means to shelter the individuals who own and run the corporation from possible legal consequences of acts by the corporation. It is worth noting that Rothbard allows a narrower definition of a corporation: ''"[...] Corporations are not at all monopolistic privileges; they are free associations of individuals pooling their capital. On the purely free market, such men would simply announce to their creditors that their liability is limited to the capital specifically invested in the corporation [...]"''{{ref|Rothbard-1962b}}  <!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/mes/chap15d.asp#_ftn11 (Rothbard 1962)] --> However, this is a very narrow definition that only shelters owners from debt by creditors that specifically agree to the arrangement.  It doesn't shelter other [[liability]], such as from malfeasance or other wrongdoing.
+
Another major problem alleged by collectivist anarchists against the ideology of anarcho-capitalism is substitution of 'opportunity' for 'freedom', in the philosophical discourse. They professes that anarcho-capitalism ignores the need to maintain the balance of freedoms, balance between positive and negative freedoms, as well as balance between freedoms of different individuals. Concentrating on a select few, anarcho-capitalists show how opportunities allowed to those few are lessened by socialism and thus conclude that socialism is unable to be free. This argument is dominant in the areas where [[state socialism]] has been a major ideology gaining or competing for dominance and happens as a result of the dominance of individualistic element in the rebellion.
  
There are limits to the right to contract under some interpretations of anarcho-capitalisim.  Rothbard himself asserts that the right to contract is based in [[inalienable rights|inalienable human rights]]{{ref|Rothbard-1982.2b}}<!-- [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/ethics/ethics.asp (Rothbard 1982,2)] --> and therefore any contract that implicitly violates those rights can be voided at will, which would, for instance, prevent a person from permanently selling himself into slavery.  Other interpretations conclude that "banning" such contracts would in itself be an unacceptably invasive interference in the right to contract.{{ref|Nozick-1973}}
+
Another profound criticism of Anarcho-capitalism is that it relies on a fundamental misunderstanding of the nature of Capitalism and its present and historical relation to the state. Study of history and indeed archaeology demonstrate that far from being in opposition, the state and Capitalism are intrinsically linked and formed together historically speaking. Historical and archaeological evidence demonstrate that prior to the development of the state and government, markets did not exist, at least not in any shape resembling that of capitalist mode of production.
  
===Systems of justice===
+
==Anarcho-capitalist criticism of socialism==
 +
Taken from the [http://www.ozarkia.net/bill/anarchism/faq.html Anarcho Capitalist FAQ]. All of these points are answered from the socialist side on the [http://francoistremblay.wordpress.com/2010/01/10/debunking-the-so-called-myths-of-socialism/ Check your premises-Blog].
  
Anarcho-capitalists only believe in collective defense of individual liberty (i.e. courts, military or police forces) insofar as such groups are formed and paid for on an explicitly voluntary basis. According to Molinari, "Under a regime of liberty, the natural organization of the security industry would not be different from that of other industries."{{ref|Molinari-1849}}<!--[http://www.gustavedemolinari.org/GM-PS.htm (Molinari 1849)]--> Proponents point out that private systems of justice and defense ''already'' exist, naturally forming where the market is allowed to compensate for the failure of the state; private arbitration, security guards, neighborhood watch groups and so on.{{ref|Friedman-1973}} <!--[http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Libertarian/Machinery_of_Freedom/MofF_Chapter_29.html (Friedman 1973, ch29)]--> Defense of those unable to pay for such protection would be financed by charitable organizations relying on voluntary donation rather than by state institutions relying on enforced taxation.
+
"What are the myths of socialism?"
  
[[Retributive justice]], meaning retalitory force, is often a component of the contracts imagined for an anarcho-capitalist society. Some believe [[prison]]s or [[indentured servitude]] would be justifiable institutions to deal with those who violate anarcho-capitalist property relations, while others believe [[exile]] or forced [[restitution]] are sufficient.{{ref|O'Keeffe-1989}} <!--[http://www.libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/legan/legan005.pdf (O&#8217;Keeffe 1989)]-->
+
'''The just price doctrine and cost-price theories of value.'''
  
=== The use of force ===
+
The medieval notion of just price permeates socialist thought. It holds that there is a intrinsic price of a good, regardless of people's wants, needs and desires, or supply and demand. In the industrial-era form of this doctrine, the value of a good is deemed to be equal to the cost of production, usually in terms of labor time expended (see labor theory of value below). This cost-price notion was refuted in the 1800s by the marginalist revolution in economics, but nevertheless many socialists remain mired in this. The marginalist economists, notably the Austrian School, consider value to be subjective. It depends on each person and his or her particular situation and values. In the desert, one may prefer a cup of water to a diamond.
  
The axiom of non-aggression is not necessarily a [[pacifism|pacifist]] doctrine, it is a prohibition against the '''initiation''' of (interpersonal) force.  Like classical liberalism, anarcho-capitalism permits the use of force, as long as it is in the defense of persons or property.
+
'''The labor theory of value.'''
  
However, the permissible extent of this defensive use of force is an arguable point between anarcho-capitalists. Some argue that the initiator of any aggressive act should be subject to a retributive counter-attack beyond what is solely necessary to repel the aggression. The counter-argument is that such a counterattack is only legitimate insofar as it was defined in an agreement between the parties.
+
The labor theory of value (LTV) is the cost-price doctrine which holds that all value springs from labor. In other words, it purports that land, capital and entrepreneurship are all non-productive, and can impute no value to a good (except insofar as they represent past labor.) The general invalidity of all just price doctrines has already been noted. The modern (marginalist) thought is that value is not determined by cost at all, but by the subjective preferences of the buyers interacting with the available quantity of the good in question. This is known as the subjective theory of value. Even on it's own intrinsic price terms, the LTV fails to account for factors of production other than labor. Standard counter-examples abound, e.g. No matter how much time you spend producing mud-pies, they are still worthless; A fresh bottle of wine gains value simply by aging; and so on. It is possible to formulate a purely descriptive LTV, which uses labor time as the measure of the productivity of land and capital, as Kevin Carson does in part 1 of his book Studies in Mutualist Political Economy, however the usefulness of this is dubious, and the temptation to slide into the prescriptive interpretation is enormous, as Carson does without justification in part 2 of the same book.
  
Another controversial application of &#8220;defensive&#8221; aggression is the act of revolutionary violence against tyrannical regimes. Many anarcho-capitalists admire [[the American Revolution]] as the legitimate act of individuals working together to fight against [[tyranny|tyrannical]] restrictions of their liberties.  But, illustrating their general ambivalence toward war, these same people also sharply criticize the revolutionaries for the means used &mdash; taxes, [[conscription]], [[Inflation|inflationary money]] &mdash; and the inadequacy of the result: a coercive government (a state).
+
''Curiously, this interpretation of the LTV is refuted in the Critique of the Gotha Program by Marx in 1890(!)'' <ref>http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/ch01.htm</ref>
  
While some anarcho-capitalists believe forceful resistance and revolutionary violence against the state is legitimate, most believe the use of force is a dangerous tool at best, and that violent [[insurrection]] should be a last resort.
+
'''The exploitation theory.'''
  
=== The Machinery of Freedom ===
+
An ''exploitation theory'' is any theory which purports to justify the claim that one "class" exploits another. In socialist theory, the claim is that a capitalist class exploits a proletarian class. Most exploitation theories are based on the antiquated LTV notion described above. Other socialists realize the weakness of this argument, and base their exploitation theory on unequal negotiating positions. While this latter approach may explain outcomes of bargaining, it evades the relevant issue - whether the trade was voluntary. Thus this approach also fails to support the claim that (so-called) "exploitation" is undesirable or unethical.
  
[[David Friedman]] described an economic approach to anarcho-capitalism in his book ''[[The Machinery of Freedom]]''. His description differs with Rothbard's because it doesn't use moral arguments, i.e. it does not appeal to a theory of [[natural rights]] to justify itself. In Friedman's work the economic argument is sufficient to derive the principles of anarcho-capitalism. Private defence/protection agencies and courts not only defend legal rights but supply the actual content of these rights and all claims on the free market. People will have the law system they pay for, and because of [[economic efficiency]] considerations resulting from individuals' utility functions, such law will tend to be libertarian in nature but will differ from place to place and from agency to agency depending on the tastes of the people who buy the law. Also unlike other anarcho-capitalists, most notably Murray Rothbard, David Friedman has never tried to deny the theoretical cogency of the neoclassical literature on "market failure", nor has he been inclined to attack economic efficiency as a normative benchmark.
+
Note that even stipulating the "creationist" LTV, the socialist argument is insufficient for proving exploitation. It lacks an explanation of why workers voluntarily exchanging labor time for wages is exploitative. Bohm-Bawerk of the Austrian school of economics showed long ago (1884 in "Exploitation Theories") that profit from wages could be explained by interest on advanced pay, i.e. workers getting paid prior to their produce being sold.
  
== History and Influences ==
+
'''Denial of scarcity (property, money).'''
[[Image:molinari.jpg|thumb|right|[[Gustave de Molinari]] (1819-1912)]]
+
=== Liberalism ===
+
{{main|Liberalism}}
+
  
Anarcho-capitalist philosophy has drawn from many influences. The primary influence with the longest history is classical liberalism.  Classical liberals have had two main themes since [[John Locke]] first expounded the philosophy: the liberty of man, and limitations of State power. The liberty of man was expressed in terms of [[Natural Rights]], while limiting the [[State]] was based (for Locke) on a consent theory. While Locke saw the State as evolving from society via a [[social contract]], later more radical liberals saw a fundamental schism between society, the "natural" voluntary interactions of men, and State, the institution of brute force.
+
This is a favorite of utopian socialists. The purpose of property is to solve the scarcity problem - that man's desires exceed available goods. This myth simply assumes away scarcity, as if this human condition was merely an effect of a particular property system rather than a fact of reality and human nature. The socialist denial of the validity of property involves an internal contradiction and much resulting "double-think." E.g. Proudhon writes that he's against contract property, but for possession property; yet he refuses to acknowledge that his "possession" is a type of property.
  
In the [[18th century]], liberal revolutionaries in Britain and America had opposed [[statism]] without grounding it in theory, while some French economists had theorized it without endorsing it. In the [[19th century]], classical liberals led the attack against statism. One notable was [[Frederic Bastiat]] ("The Law")  who wrote, "The state is the great fiction by which everybody seeks to live at the expense of everybody else." [[Henry David Thoreau]]'s liberalism might be considered evolutionary anarchism, as when he wrote, "I heartily accept the motto,'That government is best which governs least';  and I should like to see it acted up to more rapidly and systematically. Carried out, it finally amounts to this, which also I believe,'That government is best which governs not at all'; and when men are prepared for it, that will be the kind of government which they will have."{{ref|Thoreau-1849}}
+
Another naive denial of scarcity is the claim of some socialists that a modern society can get along without money. Hayek made a living by refuting that view: in short, an economy needs the informational function of money to balance supply and demand. Without the amalgamation of the desires and preferences of the producers and consumers into price, chaos results. Shortages and surpluses abound when the communication of preferences is prevented or co-opted by rulers. Money is simply and ultimately the most liquid commodity in a market. There will always be a most liquid commodity in any market; ergo, there will be something used as money."
  
The first liberal to 'explicitly' argue to abolish monopoly government was [[Gustave de Molinari]] in [[1849]]. In his essay "The Production of Security," he argued, "No government should have the right to prevent another government from going into competition with it, or to require consumers of security to come exclusively to it for this commodity."  Molinari and this new type of anti-state liberal grounded their reasoning on liberal ideals and classical economics.  Unlike the liberalism of Locke, which saw the State as evolving from society, the anti-state liberals saw a fundamental conflict between the voluntary interations of people - society - and the instutions of force - the State.  This ''society versus State'' idea was expressed in various ways: natural society vs. artificial society, liberty vs. authority, society of contract vs. society of authority, and industrial society vs. militant society, just to name a few.{{ref|Molinari-1849b}}<!-- [http://www.gustavedemolinari.org/GM-PS.htm (Molinari 1849)]--> The anti-state liberal tradition in Europe and the United States continued after Molinari in the early writings of [[Herbert Spencer]], as well as in thinkers such as [[Paul Émile de Puydt]] and [[Auberon Herbert]].
+
The obvious counter to this is that capitalists have a similarly naiive belief in the failings of human nature, believing that the animal nature underlying it is paramount and can at best be appeased with large amounts of EVERYTHING. Even if all human reason and willpower is set aside, the fact that humans represent the pinnacle of mammalian evolution, and mammals the pinnacle of animal evolution, and that mammals are most succinctly described as animals that take care of their own, still completely evades capitalists.
  
Later, in the early 20th century, the mantle of anti-state liberalism was taken by the "[[Old Right]]."  These were minarchist, anti-war, anti-imperialist, and (later) anti-[[New Deal]]ers.  Some of the most notable members of the Old Right were [[Albert Jay Nock]], [[Rose Wilder Lane]], [[Isabel Paterson]], [[Frank Chodorov]], [[Garet Garrett]], and [[H. L. Mencken]].  In the 1950's, the new "fusion conservatism," also called [[cold war]] conservatism, took hold of the right wing in the US, stressing anti-communism, militarism, and economic interventionism.  This induced the libertarian Old Right to split off from the right, and seek alliances with the (now left-wing) anti-war movement, and to start specifically libertarian organizations such as the (US) Libertarian Party.
+
== Quotations ==
 +
''"The direct use of physical force is so poor a solution to the problem of limited resources that it is commonly employed only by small children and great nations."''
 +
- '''David Friedman'''
  
[[Image:LysanderSpooner.jpg|thumb|left|[[Lysander Spooner]] (1808-1887)]]
 
  
=== Individualist anarchism ===
+
''"Because the free market system is so weak politically, the forms of capitalism that are experienced in many countries are very far from the ideal. They are a corrupted version, in which powerful interests prevent competition from playing its natural, healthy role."''
{{main|Individualist anarchism and anarcho-capitalism}}
+
- '''Raghuram G. Rajan'''
  
Anarcho-capitalist thought claims influence from the work of the 19th century [[individualist anarchists]], although the extent of this influence is a matter of some controversy.  Some of the most notable figures in this respect include [[Lysander Spooner]] and [[Benjamin Tucker]]. Of particular importance to anarcho-capitalists are the ideas of "sovereignty of the individual" (often called "self-ownership"), a right to own the product of one's labor and trade it in a free market, and the opposition to [[collectivism]] including collectivist conceptions of property, in favor of individual private property.
 
  
Lysander Spooner's articles, such as [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/notreason.htm ''No Treason''] and the [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/LetterToBayard.htm Letter to Thomas Bayard], were widely reprinted in early anarcho-capitalist journals, and his ideas -- especially his individualist critique of the state and his defense of the right to ignore or withdraw from it -- were often cited by anarcho-capitalists. Spooner was staunchly opposed to government interference in economic matters, and supported a "right to acquire property...as one of the natural, inherent, inalienable rights of men [...] one which government has no power to infringe [...]"{{ref|Spooner-1843}}<!--[http://www.lysanderspooner.org/constitutionallaw.htm (Spooner 1843)]-->.  Like all anarchists, he opposed government regulation: "All legislative restraints upon the rate of interest, are  arbitrary and tyrannical restraints upon a man's natural capacity amid natural right to hire capital, upon which to bestow his labor"{{ref|Spooner-1846}}<!--[http://www.lysanderspooner.org/Poverty.htm (Spooner 1846)]-->. He was particularly vocal, however, in opposing any collusion between banks and government, and argued that the monopolistic privileges that the government granted to a few bankers were the source of many social and economic ills.
+
''"A robust capitalism would help us to reap all the dynamic, wealth-generating energies that Marx wrote about and only the faux Marxists today deny or deplore."''
 +
- '''Jagdish Bhagwati'''
  
Benjamin Tucker supported private ownership of all wealth produced by an individual, which he believed entailed a rejection of both collective ownership and private investment of property for profit.  He was a staunch advocate of the mutualist form of private property, which holds to the labor theory of value.  He also advocated a free [[market economy]], which he believed was obstructed by the state and the profit making seen in capitalism.  From an essay in ''The New Freewoman'': "Anarchism is a word without meaning, unless it includes the liberty of the individual to control his product or whatever his product has brought him through exchange in a free market&#8212;that is, private property." Tucker characterized the economic demands of individualism as "Absolute Free Trade; free trade at home, as well as with foreign countries; the logical carrying out of the Manchester doctrine; ''laissez faire'' the universal rule"{{ref|Tucker-1888}}. Although his self-identification as a socialist and sympathy for the [[labor movement]] led to hostility from some early anarcho-capitalists (such as [[Robert LeFevre]]), others (such as [[Murray Rothbard]]) embraced his critique of the State and claimed that he defined his "socialism" not in terms of opposition to a free market or private property, but in opposition to government privileges for business.
 
  
There are several points of similarity and divergence between individual anarchism and anarcho-capitalism.
+
''"Critics of anarcho-capitalism sometimes assume that communal or worker-owned firms would be penalized or prohibited in an anarcho-capitalist society. It would be more accurate to state that while individuals would be free to voluntarily form communitarian organizations, the anarcho-capitalist simply doubts that they would be widespread or prevalent. However, in theory an "anarcho-capitalist" society might be filled with nothing but communes or worker-owned firms, so long as these associations were formed voluntarily."''
 +
- '''Bryan Caplan'''
  
::* Both philosophies favor individual private property including capital. However, individualist anarchists opposed titles to unused land, and income from the lending of capital, since that would be income without labor.
 
  
::* Both individualist anarchists and anarcho-capitalists advocate "free banking" where any individual or group of individualists would be allowed to create and lend private currency.
+
''"Capital as such is not evil; it is its wrong use that is evil. Capital in some form or other will always be needed."''
 +
- '''[[Mahatma Gandhi]]'''
  
::* Anarcho-capitalists have no ethical objection to wages being diminished by a profit allowance if both parties agree to such an arrangement. Individualist anarchists regard profit being deducted from wages as exploitative, but oppose forcibly intervening in such a contract.
 
  
::* Both individualist anarchists and anarcho-capitalists advocate private "defense associations" and private courts, though they disagree on some aspects of their jurisdiction.
+
''"Miss Goldman is a communist; I am an individualist. She wishes to destroy the right of property, I wish to assert it. I make my war upon privilege and authority, whereby the right of property, the true right in that which is proper to the individual, is annihilated. She believes that co-operation would entirely supplant competition; I hold that competition in one form or another will always exist, and that it is highly desirable it should.''"
 +
- '''[[Voltairine de Cleyre]]''', ''In Defense of Emma Goldman and the Right of Expropriation''
  
::* The individualist anarchists tended to consider "usury" (i.e., profits from labor, rent, or interest) to be an unjust source of income made possible by government-backed monopolies.  Interestingly, Tucker eventually argued that usury was possible even in the absence of the state, if vast concentrations of wealth had been accumulated due to government-backed monopolies.  Anarcho-capitalists believe that profit earned through consentual interactions are permissible, and generally praiseworthy.
 
  
[[Image:Murray Rothbard Smile.JPG|thumb|right| [[Murray Rothbard]] (1926-1995)]]
+
''"Capitalistic Anarchism? Oh, yes, if you choose to call it so. Names are indifferent to me; I am not afraid of bugaboos. Let it be so, then, capitalistic Anarchism.''"
 +
- '''Voltairine de Cleyre'''
  
=== The Austrian School  ===
 
{{main|Austrian School}}
 
The [[Austrian school]] of economics was founded with the publication of [[Carl Menger]]'s [[1871]] book, [[Principles of Economics]].  The Austrians approach economics as an a priori system like logic or mathematics, rather than as an empirical science like geology.  It attempts to discover axioms of human action (called "praxeology" in the Austrian tradition), and make deductions therefrom.  Some of these praxeological axioms are:
 
::*Humans act.
 
::*Humans prefer more of a good to less.
 
::*Humans prefer to receive a good sooner rather than later.
 
::*Each party to a trade benefits ex ante.
 
These are macro-level generalizations, or heuristics, which are true for the many, but not necessarily true for any particular person.
 
  
Even in the early days, Austrian economics was used as a theoretical weapon against socialism and statist socialist policy. Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, a colleague of Menger, wrote one of the first critiques of socialism ever written in his treatise, "The Exploitation Theory of Socialism-Communism."  Later, [[Friedrich Hayek]] wrote "The Road to Serfdom," asserting that a command economy destroys the information function of prices, and that authority over the economy leads to totalitarianism. Another very influential Austrian economist was [[Ludwig von Mises]], author of the praxeological work "Human Action."
+
''"I should say that when people talk about capitalism it's a bit of a joke. There's no such thing. No country, no business class, has ever been willing to subject itself to the free market, free market discipline. Free markets are for others. Like, the Third World is the Third World because they had free markets rammed down their throat. Meanwhile, the enlightened states, England, the United States, others, resorted to massive state intervention to protect private power, and still do. That's right up to the present. I mean, the Reagan administration for example was the most protectionist in post-war American history. Virtually the entire dynamic economy in the United States is based crucially on state initiative and intervention: computers, the internet, telecommunication, automation, pharmaceutical, you just name it. Run through it, and you find massive ripoffs of the public, meaning, a system in which under one guise or another the public pays the costs and takes the risks, and profit is privatized. That's very remote from a free market. Free market is like what India had to suffer for a couple hundred years, and most of the rest of the Third World."'' - '''[[Noam Chomsky]]''' (Talk titled "Sovereignty and World Order" at Kansas State University, September 20, 1999)
  
Murray Rothbard, a student of Mises, is the man who attempted to meld Austrian economics with classical liberalism and individualist anarchism, and is credited with coining the term "anarcho-capitalism."  He was probably the first to use "libertarian" in its current (US) pro-capitalist sense.  He was a trained economist, but also knowledgable in history and political philosophy.  When young, he considered himself part of the Old Right, an anti-statist and anti-interventionist branch of the US Republican party.  When interventionist cold warriors of the National Review, such as [[William Buckley]], captured the Republican party in the 1950s, Rothbard quit that group and formed an alliance with left-wing anti-war groups.  Later, Rothbard was a founder of the US Libertarian Party.  In the sixties, Rothbard was a part of Ayn Rand's objectivist group, but later had a falling out.  Rothbard's books, such as "Man Economy and State", "Power and Market", "The Ethics of Liberty", and "For a New Liberty", are considered by some to be classics of natural law libertarian thought.
 
  
''See also:'' Roberta Modugno Crocetta: [http://www.mises.org/journals/scholar/Modugno.PDF The anarcho-capitalist political theory of Murray N. Rothbard in its historical and intellectual context ]
+
''"Ideologies fight over the best solution to our problems. Capitalism is the recognition that this one best answer does not exist. Capitalism says that all peaceful ideas, projects and systems are welcome. It says "we don’t know the one best way," so people have to decide themselves what might be best for them, what kind of ideas and dreams they want to realise and what kinds of goods and services they should or shouldn't consume. You are free to try anything so long as you don’t use force against other people or force them to pay for your projects. Capitalism is the system that leaves the economic decisions to the people, instead of the system."''
 +
- '''Johan Norberg,''' former left-anarchist with the Anarchist Front
  
== Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism ==
+
<table style="background-color: azure; border:1px dotted #000000;padding:2px;margin:2px;width:50%">
+
''"Capitalism is the fullest expression of anarchism, and anarchism is the fullest expression of capitalism."'' - '''Murray Rothbard'''
<tr><td>
+
*''For critiques of libertarianism in general, see: [[Criticism of libertarianism]]''
+
*''For critiques of capitalism from an anarchist (anarcho-socialist) perspective, see: [[Anarchism and capitalism]]''
+
*''For the spectrum of political ideologies in relation to capitalism see: [[Capitalism and related political ideologies]]''
+
</tr></td></table>
+
Anarcho-capitalism is a radical development of liberalism.  Therefore, the same general arguments for and against [[liberalism]], [[laissez-faire capitalism]] and [[capitalism]] apply, excepting those points (such as the justice system) where anarcho-capitalism diverges from the classical liberal tradition.
+
  
===Questions of definition===
 
  
A principal tenet of anarcho-capitalism is that it regards the state as the sole purveyor of force and oppresion. The development of anarcho-capitalism originated from [[classical liberalism]] or [[libertarianism]], and is more often seen as contrasting traditional anarchism than sharing the same ideals. In its embrace of capitalist economics, "anarcho"-capitalism has been argued to contradict[[anarchism]], which has historically been ''anti''-capitalist.  Anarchists generally argue that "anarcho"-capitalism isn't a form of [[anarchism]] at all, because it denies a central basis of anarchism in the abolition of hierarchy. Anarchists often believe that capitalism cannot exist without enforcement of an economic class system, thus it is impossible to remove coercive hierarchical relationships from a capitalist system.
+
''"Without property there is no free personal life. Without property there is no power to act. The man who treads on strange ground, touches strange property at every movement he makes is not a free man. And the word 'property' must be taken literally as ownership, or, as we say to-day, private property. Without private property there is no freedom."'' - '''Emil Brunner'''
  
  
===Practical questions===
+
''"The purchaser draws boundaries, fences himself in, and says, “This is mine; each one by himself, each one for himself.” Here, then, is a piece of land upon which, henceforth, no one has a right to step, save the proprietor and his friends; which can benefit nobody, save the proprietor and his servants. Let these sales multiply, and soon the people — who have been neither able nor willing to sell, and who have received none of the proceeds of the sale — will have nowhere to rest, no place of shelter, no ground to till. They will die of hunger at the proprietor’s door, on the edge of that property which was their birthright; and the proprietor, watching them die, will exclaim, “So perish idlers and vagrants!”"'' - '''[[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]]''' (Ch. III: "Labor as the Efficient Cause of the Domain of Property")
  
Critics often assert that anarcho-capitalism will degenerate into [[plutocracy]] or [[feudalism]] in practice.  They argue that it is a rational economic decision for organizations with the ability to exert coercion (private police, security and military forces) to exploit groups with less power. In this kind of environment, [[piracy]], military [[imperialism]], and [[slavery]] can be very profitable.  Taken to its logical extreme, this argument assumes that allowing such &#8220;security&;#8221; organizations to exert coercive power will inevitably lead to their becoming a de-facto state.
 
  
[[Minarchism|Minarchist]] and [[statism|statist]] critics often argue that the [[free rider problem]] makes anarcho-capitalism (and, by extension, any [[anti-statism|anti-statist]] political system) fundamentally unworkable in modern societies. They typically argue that there are some vital goods or services &mdash; such as civil or military defense, management of common environmental resources, or the provision of [[public good]]s such as roads or lighthouses &mdash; that cannot be effectively delivered without the backing of a government exercising effective territorial control, and so that abolishing the state as anarcho-capitalists demand will either lead to catastrophe or to the eventual re-establishment of monopoly governments as a necessary means to solving the [[coordination problem]]s that the abolition of the state created.  One counter-argument by free market economists, such as [[Alex Tabarrok]], emphasizes the private use of [[assurance contracts|dominant assurance contracts]].
+
''"Property is robbery!"'' - '''Pierre-Joseph Proudhon,''' ''"Method Pursued in this Work. The Idea of a Revolution"''
  
===Moral questions===
 
  
Anarcho-capitalists consider a choice or action to be "voluntary," in a moral sense, so long as that choice or action is not influenced by coercion or fraud perpetrated by another individual. Thus, so long as an employee and employer agree to terms without aggression being used, employment is regarded as voluntary.  Some critics say this ignores constraints on action due to non-human factors, such as the need for food and shelter.  Thus, if a person requires employment in order to feed and house himself, it is said that the employer-employee relationship cannot be voluntary, even if employment was not coerced by another individual.  This is essentially a semantic argument over the term &quot;voluntary." Anarcho-capitalists simply do not use the term in that latter sense in their philosophy, believing that sense to be morally irrelevant. Other critics argue that employment is involuntary because the unfair distributions of wealth that make it necessary are supported by private property systems. This is a deeper arguement relating to [[distributive justice]].  Some of these critics appeal to an [[distributive justice|end-state theory]] of justice, while anarcho-capitalists (and [[propertarian]]s in general) appeal to an [[distributive justice|entitlement theory]]. Finally, some critics regard private property itself to be an aggressive institution, rather than a defensive one, and thus reject claims that relationships based on unequal private property relations could be "voluntary".
+
''"It will probably surprise many who know nothing of Proudhon save his declaration that 'property is robbery' to learn that he was perhaps the most vigorous hater of Communism that ever lived on this planet. But the apparent inconsistency vanishes when you read his book and find that by 'property' he means simply '''legally privileged''' wealth or power of usury, and not at all the possession of by the laborer of his products."''
 +
- '''Benjamin Tucker'''
  
Critics also point out that anarcho-capitalist ethics does not enforce any positive moral obligation to help others in need (see ''[[altruism]]'', the ethical doctrine).  Like other [[right libertarianism|right libertarians]], anarcho-capitalists may argue that no such moral obligation exists or argue that if a moral obligation to help others does exist that there is an overarching moral obligation to refrain from initiating coercion on individuals to enforce it. Anarcho-capitalists believe that helping others should be a matter of free personal choice, and do not recognise any form of social obligation arising from an individual's presence in a society. They, like all right libertarians, believe that only [[negative rights]] should be recognized as being legitimate, as opposed to [[positive rights]].  Critics often dismiss this stance as being unethical or selfish, or reject the distinction between "positive" and "negative" rights.
 
  
[[Property]] ownership rights and their extent are a source of contention among different philosophies.  Most see the rights as less absolute than anarcho-capitalists do. The main issues are 1) what kinds of things are valid property, and 2) what constitutes abandonment of property.  The first is contentious even among anarcho-capitalists: there is disagreement over the validity of intellectual property{{ref|McElroy-1995}} - non-tangible goods that are not economically scarce.  Some supporters of private property but critics of anarcho-capitalism may question whether unused land is valid property ([[Agorism]],[[Georgism]], [[Geolibertarianism]], [[Individualist anarchism]]).  The second issue, what constitutes abandonment, is a common objection among socialists who don't believe in absentee  ownership.  Anarcho-capitalists have strong abandonment criteria - one maintains ownership (more or less) until one agrees to trade  or gift it.  The critics of this view tend have weaker abandonment criteria, e.g. one loses ownership (more or less) when one stops personally using it. Also, the idea of original appropriation is anathema to most types of [[socialism]], as well as any philosophy that takes common ownership of land and [[natural resources]] as a premise.  Many philosophies view any ownership claims on land and natural resources as immoral and illegitimate.
+
''"Private property is the greatest revolutionary force which exists, with an unequaled capacity for setting itself against authority... and the principal function of private property within the political system is to act as a counterweight to the power of the State, and by so doing to insure the liberty of the individual."''
 +
- '''Pierre-Joseph Proudhon,''' ''Theory of Property''
  
[[Natural Law]] anarcho-capitalism (such as that advocated by Rothbard) is also criticized by those who have a different view on what exactly is "natural law", and by those who believe that natural laws or rights do not exist (i.e., that laws and rights are a human invention, a product of human society).  This includes criticism by [[consequentialist|consequentialists]] such as [[Milton Friedman]].
+
== External links ==
  
Utilitarian critics simply argue that anarcho-capitalism does not maximize utility; contending that it would fall far short of that goal. This kind of criticism comes from a variety of different political views and ideologies, and different critics have different views on which other system does or would do a better job of bringing the greatest benefits to the greatest number of people.  Anarcho-capitalists consider the non-aggression axiom to be a "side-constraint" on civilized human action{{ref|Nozick-1973.2}}, or a necessary condition for human society to be beneficial ([[Herbert Spencer]], [[Ayn Rand]], Murray Rothbard), and thus should not be used as a trade-off for miscellaneous utilitarian values.
+
=== Anarcho-capitalist links ===
 
+
== Notes ==
+
<!--
+
NOTE: Footnotes in this article use names, not numbers. Please see [[Wikipedia:Footnote3]] for details.
+
 
+
1) Assign your footnote a unique name, for example TheSun_Dec9.
+
2) Add the macro {{ref|TheSun_Dec9}} to the body of the article, where you want the new footnote.
+
3) Take note of the name of the footnote that immediately proceeds yours in the article body.
+
4) Add #{{Note|TheSun_Dec9}} to the list, immediately below the footnote you noted in step3.
+
5) Multiple footnotes to the same reference will not work: you must insert two uniquely-named footnotes.
+
 
+
  NOTE: It is important to add the Footnote in the right order in the list.
+
-->
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1988}} [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1988) "What&#8217;s Wrong with Liberty Poll; or, How I Became a Libertarian", Liberty, July 1988, p.53
+
#{{note|Hoppe-2001}} [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe|Hoppe, Hans-Hermann]] (2001) [http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe5.html "Anarcho-Capitalism: An Annotated Bibliography"] Retrieved [[23 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Hoppe-2001b}} Ibid.
+
#{{note|Hoppe-2001c}} Ibid.
+
#{{note|Wall-2004}} Wall, Richard (2004) [http://www.chomsky.info/onchomsky/20040817.htm "Who's Afraid of Noam Chomsky?"] Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1982.1}} [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1982.1) [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/lawproperty.pdf "Law, Property Rights, and Air Pollution"] Cato Journal 2, No. 1 (Spring 1982): pp. 55-99. Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1973}} [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1973) [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/newliberty.asp ''For a new Liberty''] Collier Books, A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc., New York: pp.24-25. Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1982.2}} [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1982.2) [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/ethics/ethics.asp ''The Ethics of Liberty''] Humanities Press ISBN 0814775063:p162 Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Heider}} Heider, Ulrike (1994) [http://www.noblesoul.com/orc/books/other/anarchism.html ''Anarchism: Left, Right, and Green''] City Lights Books ISBN 0872862895 Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Hoppe-2002}} [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe|Hoppe, Hans-Hermann]] (2002) [http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe7.html "Rothbardian Ethics"] Retrieved [[23 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Hoppe-2002b}} Ibid.
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1962}} [[Murray Rothbard|Rothbard, Murray N.]] (1962) [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/mes.asp ''Man, Economy & State with Power and Market''] Ludwig von Mises Institute ISBN 0945466307:ch2 Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1962b}} Ibid, [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/mes/chap15d.asp#_ftn11 ch15]
+
#{{note|Rothbard-1982.2b}} (Rothbard 1982.2)
+
#{{note|Nozick-1973}} [[Robert Nozick|Nozick, Robert]] (1973) ''Anarchy, State, and Utopia''
+
#{{note|Molinari-1849}} [[Gustave de Molinari|Molinari, Gustave de]] (1849) [http://www.gustavedemolinari.org/GM-PS.htm The Production of Security] ''(trans. J. Huston McCulloch)'' Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Friedman-1973}} [[David Friedman|Friedman, David D.]] (1973) ''[[The Machinery of Freedom|The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism]]'' Harper & Row ISBN 0060910100:[http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Libertarian/Machinery_of_Freedom/MofF_Chapter_29.html ch29]
+
#{{note|O'Keeffe-1989}} O&#8217;Keeffe, Matthew (1989) [http://www.libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/legan/legan005.pdf "Retribution versus Restitution"] Legal Notes No.5, Libertarian Alliance ISBN 1870614224 Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Molinari-1849b}} (Molinari 1849)
+
#{{note|Thoreau-1849}} Thoreau, Henry David (1849) [http://www.cs.indiana.edu/statecraft/civ.dis.html Civil Disobedience]
+
#{{note|Spooner-1843}} [[Lysander Spooner|Spooner, Lysander]] (1843) [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/constitutionallaw.htm ''Constitutional law, Relative to Credit, Currency, and Banking''] Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Spooner-1846}} [[Lysander Spooner|Spooner, Lysander]] (1846) [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/Poverty.htm ''Poverty: Its Illegal Causes and Cure''] Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Tucker-1888}} [[Benjamin Tucker|Tucker, Benjamin]] (1888) [http://praxeology.net/BT-SSA.htm ''State Socialism and Anarchism:How Far They Agree, and Wherein They Differ''] Liberty 5.16, no. 120 ([[10 March]] [[1888]]), pp. 2-3.Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|McElroy-1995}} McElroy, Wendy (1995) [http://www.libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/libhe/libhe014.htm Intellectual Property:The Late Nineteenth Century Libertarian Debate] Libertarian Heritage No. 14 ISBN 1856372812 Retrieved [[24 June]] [[2005]]
+
#{{note|Nozick-1973.2}}(Nozick 1973)
+
 
+
== References ==
+
* [[Lysander Spooner|Spooner, Lysander]] (1867) [http://www.lysanderspooner.org/notreason.htm ''No Treason: The Constitution of No Authority''] Retrieved [[19 May]] [[2005]]
+
* [[Benjamin Tucker|Tucker, Benjamin]] (1888) [http://praxeology.net/BT-SSA.htm ''State Socialism and Anarchism:How Far They Agree, and Wherein They Differ''] Liberty 5.16, no. 120 ([[10 March]] [[1888]]), pp. 2-3.Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
* [[Benjamin Tucker|Tucker, Benjamin]] (1926) [http://flag.blackened.net/daver/anarchism/tucker/tucker37.html ''Labor and its Pay''] Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
* [http://homepage.mac.com/dmhart/Molinari/ Gustave de Molinari and the Anti-Statist Liberal Tradition]
+
* [[Murray Rothbard|Murray N. Rothbard]]: ''[[For a New Liberty|For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto]]''
+
* [[Murray Rothbard|Murray N. Rothbard]]: ''[[The Ethics of Liberty]]''
+
* [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe]]: ''[[A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism]]''
+
* [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe]]: ''[[Democracy: The God That Failed]]''
+
* [[Bruce Benson]]: ''[[The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without The State]]''
+
* [[Linda and Morris Tannehill]]: ''[[The Market For Liberty]]''
+
 
+
 
+
== External links ==
+
=== Anarcho-capitalism websites ===
+
* [http://www.anarchism.net/ Anarchism.Net] sells books
+
* [http://home.arcor.de/danneskjoeld/ Ancapistan Network] comes with an ancap start-up, articles and links
+
* [[Anti-State.com]][http://www.anti-state.com/], has one of the more active forums and infrequent theoretical and practical articles.
+
* [http://www.lemennicier.com/index.php?limba=en Bertrand Lemennicier], a renowned French anarcho-capitalist economist and [http://www.lemennicier.com/Liens/liens_sites.htm his links (English and French)]
+
* [http://www.cuthhyra.pwp.blueyonder.co.uk/ Cuthhyra] is a resource promoting anarcho-capitalism through essays, humour, quotes, links and more.
+
* Bryan Caplan's [http://www.gmu.edu/departments/economics/bcaplan/anarfaq.htm  "Anarchism Theory FAQ"] is written from the perspective of an anarcho-capitalist.
+
* [http://www.lewrockwell.com/ LewRockwell.com] is a widely read anarcho-capitalist news site with a Catholic slant.
+
* [http://www.gustavedemolinari.org/anarcres.htm The Molinari Institute]
+
* [http://www.mises.org/content/mnr.asp Murray Rothbard: A Legacy of Liberty]
+
* [http://www.panarchy.org/ Panarchy], another way of considering things that is considered by some ultimately equivalent to anarcho-capitalism.
+
* David Hart's [http://www.arts.adelaide.edu.au/personal/DHart/ClassicalLiberalism/Molinari/ToC.html Gustave De Molinari And The Anti-Statist Liberal Tradition]
+
* [http://www.liberalia.com/ Liberalia], an anarcho-capitalist site
+
* The contrast of anarcho-capitalist and [[individualist anarchism]] is a matter of some debate. For one anarcho-capitalist view, see [http://www.blackcrayon.com/essays/intro/ A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Anarchism].
+
* [http://samizdata.net/blog/ Samizdata] is a group blog by "...a varied group [ that includes ] wild-eyed anarcho-capitalists"
+
* [http://www.strike-the-root.com/ Strike The Root] is an anarcho-capitalist news site with an atheistic slant.
+
* [http://www.capital.demon.co.uk/LA/political/anarchist.htm ''Why I Call Myself A Free Market Anarchist And Why I Am One'' by Brian Miklethwait]
+
* [http://www.libertari.org/ Libertari.org] Italian libertarian/anarcho-capitalist site
+
* [http://www.bureaucrash.com Bureaucrash]
+
* [[Stephan Kinsella]]: [http://www.lewrockwell.com/kinsella/kinsella15.html ''What It Means To Be an Anarcho-Capitalist''], January 20, 2004, LewRockwell.com
+
  
=== Opposing views ===
+
*[http://economics.gmu.edu/bcaplan/anarfaq.htm Bryan Caplan's Anarchist Theory FAQ]
* [http://www.anarchy.no/ai.html The Anarchist International Website] Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/libertar/#H4 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Anarcho-capitalism]
* [http://www.infoshop.org/faq/secFcon.html Section F] of the [http://www.infoshop.org/faq/ Anarchist FAQ] is a traditional anarchist critique of anarcho-capitalism.
+
*[http://www.ozarkia.net/bill/anarchism/faq.html Anarcho-capitalist FAQ]
* Jeff Draughn's [http://www.geocities.com/CapitolHill/5065/between.html Between Anarchism and Libertarianism: Defining a New Movement] is a contemporary anarchist critique of anarcho-capitalism
+
*[http://jim.com/anarchy/ Jim.com Explanation of Anarcho-capitalism]
* [http://world.std.com/~mhuben/libindex.html The "Critiques Of Libertarianism" website] contains critiques of both libertarianism and anarcho-capitalism.
+
*[http://praxeology.net/anarcres.htm The Molinari Institute]
*[http://www.infoshop.org/fake.html Fake Anarchists and Libertarians]
+
*[http://www.freedomainradio.com/free/ Freedomain Radio]
* Within [[libertarianism]], anarcho-capitalism is contrasted with [[minarchism]]. Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism by minarchists include Robert J. Binidotto's [http://www.vix.com/objectivism/Writing/RobertBidinotto/ContradictionInAnarchism.html The Contradiction in Anarchism], and Paul Birch's [http://www.paulbirch.net/AnarchoCapitalism1.html A Fatal Instability in Anarcho-Capitalism?] and [http://www.paulbirch.net/AnarchoCapitalism2.html Anarcho-Capitalism Dissolves into City States].
+
*[http://www.anti-state.com Anti-state.com]
*[http://directory.google.com/Top/Society/Politics/Liberalism/Libertarianism/Anarcho-Capitalism/Opposing_Views/ Collection of critical articles]
+
*[http://www.blackcrayon.com Black Crayon]
 +
*[http://www.mises.org The Ludwig von Mises Institute]
  
=== Other ===
+
=== Criticism of Anarcho-capitalism ===
* Block, Walter (2003) [http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block26.html "The Non-Aggression Axiom of Libertarianism"] Retrieved [[20 May]] [[2005]]
+
* [http://rru.worldbank.org/PapersLinks/Open.aspx?id=3762 ''Anarchy and Invention: How Does Somalia's Private Sector Cope Without Government?'' (PDF version)] Something resembling rudimentary anarcho-capitalism is developing organically in Somalia [http://64.233.161.104/search?q=cache:Y6b4hmt1RicJ:rru.worldbank.org/PapersLinks/Open.aspx  HTML version]
+
*        [http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/africa/4020259.stm ''Telecoms thriving in lawless Somalia''] Somali telecommunications infrastructure without government.
+
*[http://www.somalianarchy.com SomaliAnarchy - "Defending and Celebrating Somalis' Freedom and Prosperity"] Forum and news source for discussion of real-world approximation of anarcho-capitalism now functioning in [[Somalia]]
+
* [http://www.independent.org/issues/article.asp?id=10 ''American Anarchism''] 19th Century Individualist Anarchists influence on Anarcho-Capitalism
+
* [http://www.weisbord.org/conquest10.htm American Liberal-Anarchism] from ''The Conquest of Power'', by Albert Weisbord
+
* [http://www.isil.org/resources/introduction.html The Philosophy of Liberty] (animated)
+
* [http://www.buildfreedom.com/economic/eco_4.html ''Economic Means to Freedom - Part IV: 25 Anarcho-Capitalist Things You Can Do Now!''], by Frederick Mann
+
* [http://spoirier.lautre.net/trick.html The liberal theory of power] : a solution to complete anarcho-capitalism with effective solutions to the public good problem and to practical implementation ; it is planned to be implemented by software on the web.
+
  
== See also ==
+
*[http://www.geocities.com/CapitolHill/5065/between.html Between Anarchism and Libertarianism: Defining a New Movement by Jeff Draughn]
=== Related Subjects ===
+
*[http://flag.blackened.net/liberty/lba.html Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy - by Peter Sabatini]
* [[Anarcho-capitalist literature]]
+
*[http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/dward/newrightanarchocap.html The New Right and Anarcho-capitalism, by Peter Marshall]
* [[Anarcho-capitalist terminology and symbolism]]
+
*[http://anarchism.www7.50megs.com/10.html Anarchism and Capitalism, by Andrew Flood]
* [[Classical liberalism]]
+
*[http://infoshop.org/faq/append1.html Anarchism and "Anarcho"-capitalism]
*[[Crypto-anarchism]]: The development of the [[internet]] and [[cryptography|cryptographic methods]] raises a new possibility for unregulated trades on the internet (or 'in [[cyberspace]]') called [[crypto-anarchism]]. Crypto-anarchism is still in its infancy, and it is not clear how closely it will resemble libertarianism, anarchism, or anarcho-capitalism.
+
*[http://infoshop.org/faq/append11.html Replies to Some Errors and Distortions in Bryan Caplan's "Anarchist Theory FAQ" version 5.2]  
* [[Individualist anarchism]]
+
*[http://theanarchistlibrary.org/category/topics/right-libertarian Collection of texts about "anarcho"-capitalism and right-wing "libertarianism"] (theanarchistlibrary.org)
* [[Liberalism]]
+
* [[Market liberalism]]
+
* [[Libertarianism]]
+
* [[Panarchism]]
+
* [[Free market]]
+
  
=== General ===
+
=== Commentary ===
* [[Anarchism]]
+
* [[Anarchist law]]
+
* [[Libertatia]]
+
* [[Statism]]
+
  
[[Category:Political theories]][[Category:Libertarianism]][[Category:Political movements]]
+
*[http://praxeology.net/FB-PJP-DOI.htm The Bastiat-Proudhon Debate on Interest (1849-1850)]
[[Category:Anarchism]][[Category:Economic theories]]
+
  
[[da:Anarko-kapitalisme]]
+
[[Category:Anarchism by genre]]
[[de:Anarchokapitalismus]]
+
[[Category:Anarcho-capitalism]]
[[et:Anarhokapitalism]]
+
[[Category:Libertarianism]]
[[eo:Anarki-kapitalismo]]
+
[[Category:Individualism]]
[[fr:Anarcho-capitalisme]]
+
[[nl:Anarcho-kapitalisme]]
+
[[pt:Anarco-capitalismo]]
+
[[fi:Anarkokapitalismi]]
+
[[sv:Anarkokapitalism]]
+
  
==Credits==
+
[[es:Anarcocapitalismo]]
*Original text is compilation of two texts: (1) Definition from [http://en.wikipedia.org/ Wikipedia] and (2) [http://www.infoshop.org/faq/ An Anarchist FAQ].
+
[[fr:"anarcho"-capitalisme]]
[[Category:political theories]]
+
[[it:anarco-capitalismo]]
 +
[[de:Anarcho-Kapitalismus]]

Latest revision as of 17:56, 2 October 2015

Voice of Freedom Radical Podcast logo only.png Echo of Freedom, Radical Podcast has a podcast related to this aticle
Ownership of Self
EoF

Anarcho-Capitalism is a movement self-decribing as an individualist anarchist[1] political philosophy that advocates the elimination of the state and the elevation of the individual in a free market. Anarchists that disagree with capitalism see the label as a contradiction in terms, disputing its inclusion in the spectrum of anarchism.

Some anarcho-capitalists are fundamentally against proactive physical coercion; their system has no metanormative opposition to voluntary communism or syndicalism. Others prefer that in an anarcho-capitalist society, law enforcement, courts, any formerly state-provided institutions or services that consumers demanded would be provided by voluntarily-funded or voluntarily-formed organizations, with defense and security being provided by private defense agencies or communal militias rather than through taxation, and where money is privately produced in an open market.

Deontological anarcho-capitalists, such as Murray Rothbard, claim that no state is morally justified, and that the traditional functions of the state thus ought to be provided by voluntary human interaction. Others, such as David Friedman, claim that the state is economically and socially suboptimal and that non-physically coercive human interaction yields greater Marshallian efficiency.

There are some anarcho-capitalists that do not view anarchism as requiring titles, but see it as an attitude with hyphenations merely describing the means by which they seek to attain anarchy; that is, where no human owns any human. In fact, they are more properly described as anarchists and capitalists. For instance, they view debt and monopolization as probabilities that could bring about archism, so anarchists use capitalistic methods to prevent or limit these, including to avoid business with those that do not follow ways to avoid archism, which stems from the idea that "activity produces wealth". For example, some refuse business with companies that are monopolistic or that are developing into a monopoly, and others also refuse trade with those that do not divest to an extent or release debtors every seven years, regardless of how much was owed. Indeed, a few call themselves competists, rather than capitalists, as they view competition as necessary to obtain better products (or capital).

Theory[edit]

Anarcho-capitalism is a consistent version of capitalism, where coercive public monopolies would no longer exist.

Anarcho-Capitalism embraces the free market, which contrasts with collectivistic anarchist philosophy. It should be noted that most anarcho-capitalists define the words "capitalism," "free market" and "private property" differently from collectivistic anarchists.

  • Capitalism: economic system where production is, at least, originally privately owned, where business decisions and correction are determined through the operation of a free market.
  • Free market: market where all decisions regarding transfer of possessions, including items and services, are voluntary.
  • Private possession (or property): possession gained by the invention of it, by mixing one's labor with unused and unpossessed material or material already owned by that person, by voluntary trade or as a gift.

This difference in terminology is often the basis for controversy.

Though the first self-described anarcho-capitalist was 19th century individualist anarchist Voltarine de Cleyre, anarcho-capitalism as a defined political philosophy did not emerge until the 1950s, coming out of the tradition of classical liberalism, and generally setting itself in contrast to all forms of coercion and collectivism. Murray Rothbard, an Austrian economist influenced by work of individualist anarchists like Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner, is often described as the founder of anarcho-capitalism.

Varying Views on Intellectual Property[edit]

While some Anarcho-capitalists support intellectual property, others oppose it, claiming that intellectual property infringes on physical property. They hold that intellectual property laws "in effect grant the holder the right to control the property and bodies of other people". [1] These anarcho-capitalists consider intellectual property to be equivalent to mercantilism, the system under which monarchs would grant exclusive monopolies to companies in a certain industry or territory.

Jeremy Sapienza, founder anti-state.com writes, "Is there nothing more preposterous than equating intellectual property, whatever the hell that is, with real, personal property?"[2].

Roderick T. Long argues that intellectual property violates the freedom of the speech and of the press: "To enforce copyright laws and the like is to prevent people from making peaceful use of the information they possess. If you have acquired the information legitimately (say, by buying a book), then on what grounds can you be prevented from using it, reproducing it, trading it? Is this not a violation of the freedom of speech and press?" [3]

In cases where anarcho-capitalists support intellectual property, it stems from the idea that property arrives from activity or labor, internal or external not being a subject of debate.

Lysander Spooner, who supported copyright and patents, wrote in his THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY; OR AN ESSAY ON THE RIGHT OF AUTHORS AND INVENTORS TO A PERPETUAL PROPERTY IN THEIR IDEAS [4]: "man's ideas are his property. They are his for enjoyment, and his for use. Other men do not own his ideas. He has a right, as against all other men, to absolute dominion over his ideas....So absolute is the author’s right of dominion over his ideas that he may forbid their being communicated even by human voice if he so pleases". [5]

Murray Rothbard, a defender of copyright but not patents, claimed, "Let us consider copyright. A man writes a book or composes music. When he publishes the book or sheet of music, he imprints on the first page the word “copyright.” This indicates that any man who agrees to purchase this product also agrees as part of the exchange not to recopy or reproduce this work for sale. In other words, the author does not sell his property out­right to the buyer; he sells it on condition that the buyer not reproduce it for sale. Since the buyer does not buy the property outright, but only on this condition, any infringement of the con­tract by him or a subsequent buyer is implicit theft and would be treated accordingly on the free market. The copyright is there­fore a logical device of property right on the free market....and this copyright would be per­petual, not limited to a certain number of years. Obviously, to be fully the property of an individual, a good has to be perma­nently and perpetually the property of the man and his heirs and assigns". [6]

In Linda and Morris Tannehill's "The Market for Liberty", they supported intellectual property in a number of ways. In their advocacy of private property, they state, "A man’s life is made up of time, so when he invests his time in material or intellectual property (ideas) he is investing parts of his life, thereby making that property an extension of his life." [7] In Chapter 7, they mention how free courts would be used to help an inventor in a conflict with "Handy-Dandy Kitchen Gadget". [8]

The debate over intellectual property among anarcho-capitalists is still on-going.

Wage Labor[edit]

Anarcho-capitalists state that an employer-employee relationship may be a mutually profitable form of voluntary association. They resent government as a parasite that corrupts, biases, impedes and distorts what would otherwise be peaceful fair and free associations.

Anarcho-capitalists consider that in consenting to a contract, that each party was free to refuse, the contract is voluntary and therefore legitimate and beneficial, claiming any external power that attempts to prevent such relationship is itself an oppression.

Anarcho-capitalists argue that, no matter what social organization may or may not exist, social organizations will never eliminate the basic human requirement to work in order to support themselves. Therefore an objection based on a constraint that cannot be overcome is useless to argue about and not a rational objection at all. Additionally, they argue that while someone may not be able to refuse to work in general, one has the largest diversity on the free market with regard to their employers or beginning their own business operation. What matters is that no given employer/employee contract be coercive. Thus, anarcho-capitalists believe that an individual may choose to work in any manner they wish, be it for a wage or for some other means of payment, so long as there is no coercion involved.

Criticism of Anarcho-capitalism[edit]

Freedom without Socialism is privilege and injustice and Socialism without freedom is slavery and brutality.” ~ Mihail Bakunin
Some collectivist anarchist criticism of anarcho-capitalism resembles criticism of mainstream libertarianism

Anarcho-capitalism is a view that departs from collectivistic anarchist theories in that it regards coercive public entities as unnecessary and harmful to human society, but embraces capitalist economics. Anarcho-capitalism contradicts collectivist anarchism, an anti-capitalist philosophy. Anarcho-capitalism is often considered a paradox by collectivistic anarchists, and vice-versa.

Collectivist anarchists purport that there is no form of capitalism that does not rely on the concentration of wealth and the existence of private property, and the need for defense of this property through public or private coercion. They claim that James Donald and Bryan Caplan have attempted (in the 1990s) to frame their arguments in language and documents that appear to be legitimate, because they use certain key phrases and structure and some author's attempts to have some connection to scholarly circles with anarchist legitimacy.

Another major problem alleged by collectivist anarchists against the ideology of anarcho-capitalism is substitution of 'opportunity' for 'freedom', in the philosophical discourse. They professes that anarcho-capitalism ignores the need to maintain the balance of freedoms, balance between positive and negative freedoms, as well as balance between freedoms of different individuals. Concentrating on a select few, anarcho-capitalists show how opportunities allowed to those few are lessened by socialism and thus conclude that socialism is unable to be free. This argument is dominant in the areas where state socialism has been a major ideology gaining or competing for dominance and happens as a result of the dominance of individualistic element in the rebellion.

Another profound criticism of Anarcho-capitalism is that it relies on a fundamental misunderstanding of the nature of Capitalism and its present and historical relation to the state. Study of history and indeed archaeology demonstrate that far from being in opposition, the state and Capitalism are intrinsically linked and formed together historically speaking. Historical and archaeological evidence demonstrate that prior to the development of the state and government, markets did not exist, at least not in any shape resembling that of capitalist mode of production.

Anarcho-capitalist criticism of socialism[edit]

Taken from the Anarcho Capitalist FAQ. All of these points are answered from the socialist side on the Check your premises-Blog.

"What are the myths of socialism?"

The just price doctrine and cost-price theories of value.

The medieval notion of just price permeates socialist thought. It holds that there is a intrinsic price of a good, regardless of people's wants, needs and desires, or supply and demand. In the industrial-era form of this doctrine, the value of a good is deemed to be equal to the cost of production, usually in terms of labor time expended (see labor theory of value below). This cost-price notion was refuted in the 1800s by the marginalist revolution in economics, but nevertheless many socialists remain mired in this. The marginalist economists, notably the Austrian School, consider value to be subjective. It depends on each person and his or her particular situation and values. In the desert, one may prefer a cup of water to a diamond.

The labor theory of value.

The labor theory of value (LTV) is the cost-price doctrine which holds that all value springs from labor. In other words, it purports that land, capital and entrepreneurship are all non-productive, and can impute no value to a good (except insofar as they represent past labor.) The general invalidity of all just price doctrines has already been noted. The modern (marginalist) thought is that value is not determined by cost at all, but by the subjective preferences of the buyers interacting with the available quantity of the good in question. This is known as the subjective theory of value. Even on it's own intrinsic price terms, the LTV fails to account for factors of production other than labor. Standard counter-examples abound, e.g. No matter how much time you spend producing mud-pies, they are still worthless; A fresh bottle of wine gains value simply by aging; and so on. It is possible to formulate a purely descriptive LTV, which uses labor time as the measure of the productivity of land and capital, as Kevin Carson does in part 1 of his book Studies in Mutualist Political Economy, however the usefulness of this is dubious, and the temptation to slide into the prescriptive interpretation is enormous, as Carson does without justification in part 2 of the same book.

Curiously, this interpretation of the LTV is refuted in the Critique of the Gotha Program by Marx in 1890(!) [2]

The exploitation theory.

An exploitation theory is any theory which purports to justify the claim that one "class" exploits another. In socialist theory, the claim is that a capitalist class exploits a proletarian class. Most exploitation theories are based on the antiquated LTV notion described above. Other socialists realize the weakness of this argument, and base their exploitation theory on unequal negotiating positions. While this latter approach may explain outcomes of bargaining, it evades the relevant issue - whether the trade was voluntary. Thus this approach also fails to support the claim that (so-called) "exploitation" is undesirable or unethical.

Note that even stipulating the "creationist" LTV, the socialist argument is insufficient for proving exploitation. It lacks an explanation of why workers voluntarily exchanging labor time for wages is exploitative. Bohm-Bawerk of the Austrian school of economics showed long ago (1884 in "Exploitation Theories") that profit from wages could be explained by interest on advanced pay, i.e. workers getting paid prior to their produce being sold.

Denial of scarcity (property, money).

This is a favorite of utopian socialists. The purpose of property is to solve the scarcity problem - that man's desires exceed available goods. This myth simply assumes away scarcity, as if this human condition was merely an effect of a particular property system rather than a fact of reality and human nature. The socialist denial of the validity of property involves an internal contradiction and much resulting "double-think." E.g. Proudhon writes that he's against contract property, but for possession property; yet he refuses to acknowledge that his "possession" is a type of property.

Another naive denial of scarcity is the claim of some socialists that a modern society can get along without money. Hayek made a living by refuting that view: in short, an economy needs the informational function of money to balance supply and demand. Without the amalgamation of the desires and preferences of the producers and consumers into price, chaos results. Shortages and surpluses abound when the communication of preferences is prevented or co-opted by rulers. Money is simply and ultimately the most liquid commodity in a market. There will always be a most liquid commodity in any market; ergo, there will be something used as money."

The obvious counter to this is that capitalists have a similarly naiive belief in the failings of human nature, believing that the animal nature underlying it is paramount and can at best be appeased with large amounts of EVERYTHING. Even if all human reason and willpower is set aside, the fact that humans represent the pinnacle of mammalian evolution, and mammals the pinnacle of animal evolution, and that mammals are most succinctly described as animals that take care of their own, still completely evades capitalists.

Quotations[edit]

"The direct use of physical force is so poor a solution to the problem of limited resources that it is commonly employed only by small children and great nations." - David Friedman


"Because the free market system is so weak politically, the forms of capitalism that are experienced in many countries are very far from the ideal. They are a corrupted version, in which powerful interests prevent competition from playing its natural, healthy role." - Raghuram G. Rajan


"A robust capitalism would help us to reap all the dynamic, wealth-generating energies that Marx wrote about and only the faux Marxists today deny or deplore." - Jagdish Bhagwati


"Critics of anarcho-capitalism sometimes assume that communal or worker-owned firms would be penalized or prohibited in an anarcho-capitalist society. It would be more accurate to state that while individuals would be free to voluntarily form communitarian organizations, the anarcho-capitalist simply doubts that they would be widespread or prevalent. However, in theory an "anarcho-capitalist" society might be filled with nothing but communes or worker-owned firms, so long as these associations were formed voluntarily." - Bryan Caplan


"Capital as such is not evil; it is its wrong use that is evil. Capital in some form or other will always be needed." - Mahatma Gandhi


"Miss Goldman is a communist; I am an individualist. She wishes to destroy the right of property, I wish to assert it. I make my war upon privilege and authority, whereby the right of property, the true right in that which is proper to the individual, is annihilated. She believes that co-operation would entirely supplant competition; I hold that competition in one form or another will always exist, and that it is highly desirable it should." - Voltairine de Cleyre, In Defense of Emma Goldman and the Right of Expropriation


"Capitalistic Anarchism? Oh, yes, if you choose to call it so. Names are indifferent to me; I am not afraid of bugaboos. Let it be so, then, capitalistic Anarchism." - Voltairine de Cleyre


"I should say that when people talk about capitalism it's a bit of a joke. There's no such thing. No country, no business class, has ever been willing to subject itself to the free market, free market discipline. Free markets are for others. Like, the Third World is the Third World because they had free markets rammed down their throat. Meanwhile, the enlightened states, England, the United States, others, resorted to massive state intervention to protect private power, and still do. That's right up to the present. I mean, the Reagan administration for example was the most protectionist in post-war American history. Virtually the entire dynamic economy in the United States is based crucially on state initiative and intervention: computers, the internet, telecommunication, automation, pharmaceutical, you just name it. Run through it, and you find massive ripoffs of the public, meaning, a system in which under one guise or another the public pays the costs and takes the risks, and profit is privatized. That's very remote from a free market. Free market is like what India had to suffer for a couple hundred years, and most of the rest of the Third World." - Noam Chomsky (Talk titled "Sovereignty and World Order" at Kansas State University, September 20, 1999)


"Ideologies fight over the best solution to our problems. Capitalism is the recognition that this one best answer does not exist. Capitalism says that all peaceful ideas, projects and systems are welcome. It says "we don’t know the one best way," so people have to decide themselves what might be best for them, what kind of ideas and dreams they want to realise and what kinds of goods and services they should or shouldn't consume. You are free to try anything so long as you don’t use force against other people or force them to pay for your projects. Capitalism is the system that leaves the economic decisions to the people, instead of the system." - Johan Norberg, former left-anarchist with the Anarchist Front


"Capitalism is the fullest expression of anarchism, and anarchism is the fullest expression of capitalism." - Murray Rothbard


"Without property there is no free personal life. Without property there is no power to act. The man who treads on strange ground, touches strange property at every movement he makes is not a free man. And the word 'property' must be taken literally as ownership, or, as we say to-day, private property. Without private property there is no freedom." - Emil Brunner


"The purchaser draws boundaries, fences himself in, and says, “This is mine; each one by himself, each one for himself.” Here, then, is a piece of land upon which, henceforth, no one has a right to step, save the proprietor and his friends; which can benefit nobody, save the proprietor and his servants. Let these sales multiply, and soon the people — who have been neither able nor willing to sell, and who have received none of the proceeds of the sale — will have nowhere to rest, no place of shelter, no ground to till. They will die of hunger at the proprietor’s door, on the edge of that property which was their birthright; and the proprietor, watching them die, will exclaim, “So perish idlers and vagrants!”" - Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (Ch. III: "Labor as the Efficient Cause of the Domain of Property")


"Property is robbery!" - Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, "Method Pursued in this Work. The Idea of a Revolution"


"It will probably surprise many who know nothing of Proudhon save his declaration that 'property is robbery' to learn that he was perhaps the most vigorous hater of Communism that ever lived on this planet. But the apparent inconsistency vanishes when you read his book and find that by 'property' he means simply legally privileged wealth or power of usury, and not at all the possession of by the laborer of his products." - Benjamin Tucker


"Private property is the greatest revolutionary force which exists, with an unequaled capacity for setting itself against authority... and the principal function of private property within the political system is to act as a counterweight to the power of the State, and by so doing to insure the liberty of the individual." - Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Theory of Property

External links[edit]

Anarcho-capitalist links[edit]

Criticism of Anarcho-capitalism[edit]

Commentary[edit]

  • Adams, Ian. 2002. Political Ideology Today. p. 135. Manchester University Press; Ostergaard, Geoffrey. 2003. Anarchism. In W. Outwaite (Ed.), The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought. p. 14. Blackwell Publishing
  • http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/ch01.htm