Still working to recover. Please don't edit quite yet.

Wage slavery

From Anarchopedia
Revision as of 23:49, 19 October 2013 by 202.213.200.193 (Talk) (Worker cooperatives, syndicalism and self-management)

Jump to: navigation, search

Wage slavery refers to a situation where a person's livelihood depends on wages, especially when the dependence is total and immediate.[1][2] The term draws an analogy between slavery and wage labor, and may refer to an "[un]equal bargaining situation between labor and capital", particularly where workers are paid comparatively low wages (e.g. sweatshops),[3] or it may draw similarities between owning and employing a person, which equates the term with a lack of workers' self-management.[4][5][6] The latter covers a wider range of employment choices bound by the pressures of a hierarchical social environment e.g. working for a wage not only under threat of starvation or poverty, but also of social stigma or status diminution.[7][8][9]

Similarities between wage labor and slavery were noted at least as early as Cicero [10] and Aristotle.[11] With the advent of the industrial revolution, thinkers such as Proudhon and Marx elaborated these comparisons in the context of a critique of property not intended for active personal use.[12][13] Before the American Civil War, Southern defenders of African American slavery also invoked the concept of wage slavery to favorably compare the condition of their slaves to workers in the North.[14][15] The introduction of wage labor in 18th century Britain was met with resistance – giving rise to the principles of syndicalism.[16][17][18][19]

19th century female workers in Lowell, Massachusetts were arguably the first people to use the term "wage slavery"

The use of the term wage slave by labor organizations may originate from the labor protests of the Lowell Mill Girls in 1836.[20] The imagery of wage slavery was widely used by labor organizations during the mid-19th century to object to the lack of workers' self-management. However, it was gradually replaced by the more pragmatic term "wage work" towards the end of the 19th century, as labor organizations shifted their focus to raising wages.[21][22]

Historically, some labor organizations and individual social activists, have espoused workers' self-management or worker cooperatives as possible alternatives to wage labor.[5][18]

Hello! dfkcedb interesting dfkcedb site! I'm really like it! Very, very dfkcedb good!

Very nice site!

Hello! ekddgkd interesting ekddgkd site! I'm really like it! Very, very ekddgkd good!

Very nice site!

Criticism

According to Eric Foner, most abolitionists in the U.S. regarded the analogy of wage earners to slaves, symbolized by the term "wage slavery," as spurious. Abolitionist William Lloyd Garrison stated that the use of the term "wage slavery" (in a time when chattel slavery was still common) was an "abuse of language."[23] Most abolitionists believed that wage workers were "neither wronged nor oppressed".[24] Former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass described his elation when he took a paying job, declaring that "Now I am my own master." According to Douglass, wage labor did not represent oppression but fair exchange and former slaves for the first time receiving the fruits of their labor.[25]

Philosopher Gary Young has argued that the same basic reasoning that considers the individual to be forced to sell his labor to a capitalist in order to survive, also applies to the capitalist in that he is forced to hire a worker to survive otherwise his capital will be exhausted through consumption, leaving him nothing to purchase the necessities of life.[26] In this sense, the capitalists depend on the workers as the workers depend on the capitalists.[27]

In mainstream economic philosophy, wage labor is seen as the voluntary sale of one's own time and efforts, just like a carpenter would sell a chair, or a farmer would sell wheat. It is considered neither an antagonistic nor abusive relationship, and carries no particular moral implications. From this perspective, the problem of poverty comes from an unequal distribution of income and can be addressed by government programs like social security and progressive taxation, and does not reflect a fundamental flaw in the capitalist system.[28]

Wage slavery is also in contradiction to the classical liberal notion of self-ownership. Under this view, a person is not free unless he can sell himself, because if a person does not own themself, they must be owned by either another individual or a group of individuals. The ability for anyone to consent to an activity or action would then be placed in the hands of a third party. Further, the third-party's ownership would also be in the hands of yet another individual or group. This regression of ownership would transfer ad infinitum and leave no one with the ability to coordinate their own actions or those of anyone else. The conclusion is therefore that if under wage slavery, self-ownership is not legitimate, there is no right for anyone then to claim enslavement to wages in the first place.[29] Of course, wage slavery can be seen as a form of duress, in that one must be a wage slave to survive.

Employment contracts

Some criticize wage slavery on strictly contractual grounds, e.g. David Ellerman and Carole Pateman, arguing that the employment contract is a legal fiction in that it treats human beings juridically as mere tools or inputs by abdicating responsibility and self-determination, which the critics argue are inalienable. As Ellerman points out, "[t]he employee is legally transformed from being a co-responsible partner to being only an input supplier sharing no legal responsibility for either the input liabilities [costs] or the produced outputs [revenue, profits] of the employer’s business."[30] Such contracts are inherently invalid "since the person remain[s] a de facto fully capacitated adult person with only the contractual role of a non-person . . ." as it is impossible to physically transfer self-determination.[31] As Pateman argues:
"The contractarian argument is unassailable all the time it is accepted that abilities can ‘acquire’ an external relation to an individual, and can be treated as if they were property. To treat abilities in this manner is also implicitly to accept that the ‘exchange’ between employer and worker is like any other exchange of material property . . . The answer to the question of how property in the person can be contracted out is that no such procedure is possible. Labour power, capacities or services, cannot be separated from the person of the worker like pieces of property."[32]

Critics of the employment contract advocate consistently applying "the principle behind every trial," i.e., "legal responsibility should be imputed in accordance with de facto responsibility," implying a workplace run jointly by the people who actually work in the firm.[33] The people who actually work in a firm are de facto responsible for the actions of said firm and thus have a legal claim to its outputs, as the contractarian critics argue. "Responsible human action, net value-adding or net value-subtracting, is not de facto transferable."[34] Suppliers (including shareholders), on the other hand, having no de facto responsibility, have no legal claim to the outputs.

While a person may still voluntarily decide to contractually rent himself, just as today he may voluntarily decide to contractually sell himself, in a society where "the principle behind every trial" is consistently applied, neither contract would be legally enforceable, and the rented/sold individual would maintain at all times de jure responsibility for her/his actions, including legal claim to the fruits of their labor. In a modern liberal-capitalist society, the employment contract is enforced while the enslavement contract is not; the former being considered valid because of its consensual/non-coercive nature, and the later being considered inherently invalid, consensual or not. The noted economist Paul Samuelson described this discrepancy.

"Since slavery was abolished, human earning power is forbidden by law to be capitalized. A man is not even free to sell himself; he must rent himself at a wage."[35]

Some advocates of laissez-faire capitalism, among them Robert Nozick, address this inconsistency in modern societies, arguing that a consistently libertarian society would allow and regard as valid consensual/non-coercive enslavement contracts, rejecting the notion of inalienable rights.

"The comparable question about an individual is whether a free system will allow him to sell himself into slavery. I believe that it would."[36]

Others like Murray Rothbard allow for the possibility of debt slavery, asserting that a lifetime labour contract can be broken so long as the slave pays appropriate damages:

"[I]f A has agreed to work for life for B in exchange for 10,000 grams of gold, he will have to return the proportionate amount of property if he terminates the arrangement and ceases to work."[37]

See also


References

  1. wage slave - Definition from the Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary
  2. wage slave - Definitions from Dictionary.com
  3. p.184 Democracy's Discontent By Michael J. Sandel
  4. Conversation with Noam Chomsky, p. 2 of 5. Globetrotter.berkeley.edu. URL accessed on 2010-06-28.
  5. 5.0 5.1 From wage slaves to wage workers: cultural opportunity structures and the evolution of the wage demands of the Knights of Labor and the American Federation of Labor, 1880-1900. - Crime. Socialissues.wiseto.com. URL accessed on 2010-06-28.
  6. [1]Template:Dead link
  7. Full text of CANNIBALS ALL! OR, SLAVES WITHOUT MASTERS., by George Fitzhugh (1857)
  8. Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
  9. Conversation with Noam Chomsky, p. 2 of 5
  10. "...vulgar are the means of livelihood of all hired workmen whom we pay for mere manual labor, not for artistic skill; for in their case the very wage they receive is a pledge of their slavery." - De Officiis [2]
  11. ["All paid jobs absorb and degrade the mind." http://www.quotationspage.com/quote/1097.html]
  12. Marx, Ch. 7 of Theories of Surplus Value, a critique of Linguet, Théorie des lois civiles, etc., Londres, 1767.
  13. Proudhon, Pierre Joseph. What is Property? An Inquiry into the Principle of Right and of Government.
  14. Foner, Eric. Free Soil, Free Labor, Free Men, p. XIX.
  15. Jensen, Derrick. The Culture of Make Believe.
  16. [The Making of the English Working Class, p. 599]
  17. [The Making of the English Working Class, p. 912]
  18. 18.0 18.1 [Geoffrey Ostergaard, The Tradition of Workers' Control, p. 133]
  19. [Competitive Advantage on the Shop Floor, p. 37]
  20. Artisans Into Workers: Labor in Nineteenth-century America By Bruce Laurie
  21. Helga Kristin, ({{{year}}}). "From Wage Slaves to Wage Workers: Cultural Opportunity Structures and the Evolution of the Wage Demands of Knights of Labor and the American Federation of Labor, 1880-1900," Social Forces, 85, 1393–1411.
  22. From Wage Slaves to Wage Workers--Free text
  23. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named Foner.2C_Eric_1998._p._66
  24. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named McNall_95
  25. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named Douglass_95
  26. Young, Gary. 1978. Justice and Capitalist Production. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8, no. 3, p. 448
  27. Nino, Carlos Santiago. 1992. Rights. NYU Press. p.343
  28. Mankiw, N. Gregory (2002). Macroeconomics, 5th, Worth.
  29. interpersonal exchange on The Ludwig von Mises Institute accessed at March 11, 2008
  30. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 16
  31. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 14
  32. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 32
  33. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 27
  34. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 26
  35. Ellerman, David, Inalienable Rights and Contracts, 21
  36. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 2
  37. Man, Economy, and State, vol. I , p. 441

114. ^Carrier, Jerry "The Making of the Slave Class" Algora Publishing 2010

External links

Template:div col