Still working to recover. Please don't edit quite yet.
philosophical anarchism
Philosophical anarchism is an anarchist school of thought[1] which contends that the State lacks moral legitimacy but does not advocate revolution to eliminate it. Though philosophical anarchism does not necessarily imply any action or desire for the elimination of the State, philosophical anarchists do not believe that they have an obligation or duty to obey the State, or conversely, that the State has a right to command.
Philosophical anarchism is a component especially of individualist anarchism.[2] Philosophical anarchists of historical note include William Godwin, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Benjamin Tucker[3], and Henry David Thoreau[4]. Contemporary philosophical anarchists include John Simmons and Robert Paul Wolff.
According to scholar Allan Antliff, Benjamin Tucker coined the term "philosophical anarchism," to distinguish peaceful evolutionary anarchism from revolutionary variants.[5]
Variations[edit]
Philosophical anarchists may accept the existence of a minimal state as unfortunate, and usually temporary, "necessary evil" but argue that citizens do not have a moral obligation to obey the state when its laws conflict with individual autonomy.[6] As conceived by William Godwin, it requires individuals to act in accordance with their own judgments and to allow every other individual the same liberty; conceived egoistically as by Max Stirner, it implies that 'the unique one' who truly 'owns himself' recognizes no duties to others; within the limit of his might, he does what is right for him.[7]
Rather than throwing bombs or taking up arms to bring down the state, philosophical anarchists "have worked for a gradual change to free the individual from what they thought were the oppressive laws and social constraints of the modern state and allow all individuals to become self-determining and value-creating."[8] They may oppose the immediate elimination of the state by violent means out of concern that it would be left unsecured against the establishment of a more harmful and oppressive state. This is especially true among those anarchists who consider violence and the state as synonymous, or who consider it counterproductive where public reaction to violence results in increased "law enforcement" efforts.
Notable philosophical anarchists[edit]
William Godwin, the founder of philosophical anarchism,[9] believed that government was a "necessary evil" but that it will become increasingly unnecessary and powerless by the gradual spread of knowledge. Godwin said,
The nineteen century individualist anarchist Victor Yarros also stated a typical philosophical anarchist positionTemplate:Or when he said,
Similarly, philosophical anarchist Henry David Thoreau asserted
Thomas Jefferson is also sometimes seen as a philosophical anarchist[11], who said
According to philosophical anarchist John Simmons:
Philosophical anarchists may not wish to disrupt a particular state, but they do not necessarily think anyone has an obligation to obey the state. According to philosophical anarchist Robert Paul Wolff, there can be no such thing as a government which "has a right to command and whose subjects have a binding obligation to obey."[13]
Mahatma Gandhi also identified himself as a philosophical anarchist.[1]
Notes[edit]
- ↑ Wayne Gabardi, review of Anarchism by David Miller, published in American Political Science Review Vol. 80, No. 1. (Mar., 1986), pp. 300-302.
- ↑ Outhwaite, William & Tourain, Alain (Eds.). (2003). Anarchism. The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought (2nd Edition, p. 12). Blackwell Publishing
- ↑ Tucker, Benjamin R., Instead of a Book, by a Man too Busy to Write One: A Fragmentary Exposition of Philosophical Anarchism (1897, New York)
- ↑ Broderick, John C. Thoreau's Proposals for Legislation. American Quarterly, Vol. 7, No. 3 (Autumn, 1955). p. 285
- ↑ Antliff, Allan. 2001. Anarchist Modernism: Art, Politics, and the First American Avant-Garde. University of Chicago Press. p.4
- ↑ Klosko, George. Political Obligations. Oxford University Press 2005. p. 4
- ↑ Outhwaite, William & Tourain, Alain (Eds.). (2003). "Anarchism," in The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought. (2nd Edition, p. 12). Blackwell Publishing
- ↑ Murphy, Brenda. The Provincetown Players and the Culture of Modernity. Cambridge University Press 2005. pp. 31-32.
- ↑ Template:sep entry
- ↑ Wasserman, Louis. Modern Political Philosophies and What They Mean. Haleyon House 1944. p. 120
- ↑ 11.0 11.1 Adler, Mortimer Jerome. The Great Ideas. Open Court Publishing 2000. p. 378
- ↑ Cited in Wetman, Cristopher Heath. Is There a Duty to Obey the Law? Cambridge University Press. 2005. pp. 24-25.
- ↑ Cited in Wolff's "Defence of Philosophical Anarchism" by Rex Martin. Philosophical Quarterly, Vol 24 No 95, April 1974, p. 141
External links[edit]
This article contains content from Wikipedia. Current versions of the GNU FDL article philosophical anarchism on WP may contain information useful to the improvement of this article | WP |